02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Does Bradley’s Regress Support Nom<strong>in</strong>alism?<br />

Wolfgang Freitag, Konstanz, Germany<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard arguments aga<strong>in</strong>st realism about<br />

universals is based on Bradley’s regress. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to this<br />

argument, realism about universals is committed to a<br />

vicious regress of <strong>in</strong>stantiation relations. If realism is false<br />

<strong>and</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>alism <strong>the</strong> only alternative, <strong>the</strong>n, so <strong>the</strong> argument<br />

concludes, nom<strong>in</strong>alism is correct. The strength of this<br />

argumentation depends on three th<strong>in</strong>gs: (1) that<br />

commitment to Bradley’s regress makes a position<br />

untenable; (2) that nom<strong>in</strong>alism as <strong>the</strong> only alternative to<br />

realism is not committed to <strong>the</strong> regress; <strong>and</strong>, most<br />

importantly, (3) that realism is committed to <strong>the</strong> regress.<br />

I have three aims <strong>in</strong> this paper. My proximate aim is<br />

to show that if (3) is correct <strong>the</strong>n (2) is <strong>in</strong>correct: if <strong>the</strong> realist<br />

is committed to Bradley’s regress <strong>the</strong>n so is at least one<br />

version of nom<strong>in</strong>alism, namely, trope <strong>the</strong>ory. The demonstration<br />

that nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ory is committed to <strong>the</strong> regress<br />

(<strong>and</strong> hence that (3) is false) is my second aim, atta<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

<strong>the</strong> proof that <strong>the</strong>se positions have no commitment to a<br />

condition which is generally (<strong>and</strong> rightly!) held to be necessary<br />

for Bradley’s regress. As I move along, I shall also<br />

claim that <strong>the</strong>re is a widely ignored second condition necessary<br />

for <strong>the</strong> regress, to which – aga<strong>in</strong> – nei<strong>the</strong>r nom<strong>in</strong>alism<br />

nor realism has any commitment. The upshot is this:<br />

Bradley’s regress problem is <strong>in</strong>dependent of <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

of universals. I conclude with an attempt to expla<strong>in</strong> why<br />

many philosophers have been misled <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>rwise.<br />

1. The regress argument, realism <strong>and</strong><br />

nom<strong>in</strong>alism<br />

Here, I shall discuss solely nom<strong>in</strong>alism <strong>and</strong> realism concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

universals, which are understood to be nonrelational<br />

or relational properties. 1 For <strong>the</strong> sake of simplicity, I<br />

will focus on nonrelational properties.<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> tradition, I take realism about universals<br />

to be <strong>the</strong> view that different objects may have <strong>the</strong> very<br />

same, repeatable property. If both <strong>the</strong> bike <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> car are<br />

black, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> realist says <strong>the</strong>re is one <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same<br />

property, blackness, <strong>in</strong>stantiated by both <strong>the</strong> bike <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

car. Thus, accord<strong>in</strong>g to realism about universals, a s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

property may be multiply <strong>in</strong>stantiated <strong>in</strong> a given world.<br />

Nom<strong>in</strong>alism denies this. If <strong>the</strong> bike <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> car are black,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y do not literally speak<strong>in</strong>g have <strong>the</strong> same property<br />

<strong>in</strong> common. The class nom<strong>in</strong>alist, for example, considers<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g black as no more than be<strong>in</strong>g an element of a certa<strong>in</strong><br />

class of particulars. Instantiation of a property <strong>the</strong>n reduces<br />

to membership <strong>in</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> class. The trope <strong>the</strong>orist<br />

assumes properties to be much as <strong>the</strong> realist th<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>the</strong>m<br />

to be, except that <strong>the</strong>y are not repeatable: <strong>in</strong> a given world,<br />

no two particulars have literally <strong>the</strong> same property.<br />

I have encountered <strong>the</strong> Bradley argument, employed<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st realism about universals, frequently <strong>in</strong> personal<br />

discussions, <strong>and</strong> sometimes <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>t. A very recent<br />

formulation of <strong>the</strong> argument by Gonzalo Rodriguez-<br />

1 Sometimes <strong>the</strong> dispute is taken to concern not <strong>the</strong> question of universals <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> above sense, but that of <strong>the</strong> existence of abstract entities. Qu<strong>in</strong>e even<br />

uses <strong>the</strong> term ‘universal’ as synonymous with ‘abstract entity’. I shall not enter<br />

this different dispute.<br />

Pereyra, a proponent of nom<strong>in</strong>alism, gives me an opportunity<br />

to voice my own view on <strong>the</strong> matter: 2<br />

[One argument aga<strong>in</strong>st universals is this:] Suppose<br />

<strong>the</strong>re are universals, both monadic <strong>and</strong> relational, <strong>and</strong><br />

that when an entity <strong>in</strong>stantiates a universal, or a<br />

group of entities <strong>in</strong>stantiate a relational universal, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are l<strong>in</strong>ked by an <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation. Suppose now<br />

that a <strong>in</strong>stantiates <strong>the</strong> universal F. S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

many th<strong>in</strong>gs that <strong>in</strong>stantiate many universals, it is<br />

plausible to suppose that <strong>in</strong>stantiation is a relational<br />

universal. But if <strong>in</strong>stantiation is a relational universal,<br />

when a <strong>in</strong>stantiates F, a, F <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation<br />

are l<strong>in</strong>ked by an <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation. Call this <strong>in</strong>stantiation<br />

relation i2 (<strong>and</strong> suppose it, as is plausible,<br />

to be dist<strong>in</strong>ct from <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation (i1) that<br />

l<strong>in</strong>ks a <strong>and</strong> F). Then s<strong>in</strong>ce i2 is also a universal, it<br />

looks as if a, F, i1 <strong>and</strong> i2 will have to be l<strong>in</strong>ked by ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

<strong>in</strong>stantiation relation i3, <strong>and</strong> so on ad <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itum.<br />

(Rodriguez-Pereyra 2008)<br />

The argument asserts that <strong>in</strong>stantiation of universals <strong>in</strong>evitably<br />

leads to a regress of ever more <strong>in</strong>stantiation relations,<br />

i.e., to what is usually referred to as Bradley’s regress.<br />

3 The claim that a regress ensues seems to be<br />

based on <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g two conditions:<br />

(Pu1) Wherever a universal is <strong>in</strong>stantiated, <strong>the</strong>re is an<br />

<strong>in</strong>stantiation relation (not identical to one of <strong>the</strong> relata).<br />

(Pu2) The <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation is a universal.<br />

Therefore it seems plausible to attribute to Rodriguez-<br />

Pereyra <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>e of thought: Accord<strong>in</strong>g to (Pu1),<br />

<strong>in</strong>stantiation of a universal dem<strong>and</strong>s an <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation.<br />

Classify<strong>in</strong>g this <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation as a universal, as<br />

done <strong>in</strong> (Pu2), we are taken back to (Pu1), which <strong>the</strong>n generates<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation, which toge<strong>the</strong>r<br />

with (Pu2) aga<strong>in</strong> takes us back to (Pu1), which generates a<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation, <strong>and</strong> so on ad <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itum. Rodriguez-Pereyra<br />

concludes that realism about universals is <strong>in</strong><br />

serious trouble. My first aim is to show that if <strong>the</strong> realist is<br />

<strong>in</strong> trouble, <strong>the</strong>n so is at least one form of nom<strong>in</strong>alism.<br />

One form of nom<strong>in</strong>alism is trope <strong>the</strong>ory. Trope <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guishes itself from realism not with respect to <strong>the</strong><br />

reality of properties, but with respect to <strong>the</strong> view that properties<br />

can be multiply <strong>in</strong>stantiated. Tropes can be <strong>in</strong>stantiated<br />

– but only by <strong>the</strong> sole object hav<strong>in</strong>g that particular<br />

trope. Tropes are “particularised” properties. Now, consider<br />

<strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g pair of conditions:<br />

(Pt1) Wherever a trope is <strong>in</strong>stantiated, <strong>the</strong>re is an <strong>in</strong>stantiation<br />

relation (not identical to one of <strong>the</strong> relata).<br />

(Pt2) The <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation is a trope.<br />

2 For o<strong>the</strong>r versions of <strong>the</strong> argument <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>t, see Devitt 1980, p. 437, Loux<br />

1998, pp. 38–40, <strong>and</strong> Morel<strong>and</strong> 2001, pp. 114–116.<br />

3 The attribution of such arguments to F. H. Bradley is historically problematic<br />

<strong>in</strong> at least two respects. Firstly, Bradley was concerned with relational properties<br />

specifically <strong>and</strong> not with properties <strong>in</strong> general. Secondly, he was not <strong>the</strong><br />

orig<strong>in</strong>ator of this l<strong>in</strong>e of thought. The general type of argument has been<br />

known at least s<strong>in</strong>ce Plato’s dialogues. See <strong>in</strong> particular Parmenides, 127e–<br />

130a.<br />

99

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!