02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

phenomenal concept of experienc<strong>in</strong>g red. This is because<br />

bra<strong>in</strong> state p2, which is my experience of red, was<br />

causally responsible for p1. Ex hypo<strong>the</strong>si, p1 <strong>and</strong> p2 are<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ct physical states. This would make it possible for a<br />

neuroscientist to stimulate p1 while ensur<strong>in</strong>g that p2 is left<br />

<strong>in</strong>ert. But what exactly is happen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this scenario? If it<br />

is anyth<strong>in</strong>g like <strong>the</strong> water case, I will th<strong>in</strong>k that I’m enterta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

a phenomenal concept that refers to p2 but I will<br />

actually be deploy<strong>in</strong>g a nonphenomenal concept of <strong>the</strong><br />

neuroscientist’s electrical stimulation. This means that I<br />

will mistakenly believe that I am th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g ‘phenomenally’<br />

about experienc<strong>in</strong>g red when I am actually th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g nonphenomenally<br />

about someth<strong>in</strong>g else.<br />

If we accept Kripke’s observation that <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

reality / appearance dist<strong>in</strong>ction when it comes to our<br />

phenomenology <strong>the</strong>n this seems highly implausible. But<br />

more importantly, it is imperative that <strong>the</strong> phenomenal<br />

concept strategist develop an account of phenomenal<br />

concepts that is genu<strong>in</strong>ely phenomenal <strong>and</strong> Lev<strong>in</strong>, by<br />

keep<strong>in</strong>g her account physically respectable, loses touch<br />

with this crucial feature. She preserves (ii) at <strong>the</strong><br />

expense of (i). This shortcom<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>ts us to a different<br />

account, one that makes <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong><br />

phenomenal concept <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> object it denotes much<br />

tighter.<br />

David Pap<strong>in</strong>eau’s account of quasi-quotational<br />

phenomenal concepts discharges this duty. His idea is to<br />

analyze phenomenal concepts as a species of<br />

perceptual concepts. Consider my ability to perceptually<br />

identify a flower <strong>and</strong> make judgments about it. I might be<br />

able to th<strong>in</strong>k ‘that flower’ is beautiful when look<strong>in</strong>g at a<br />

tulip. I have, at my disposal, a visual sensory template<br />

that I can use to recognize tulips. This template,<br />

however, is not only useful for th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about external<br />

objects like tulips, but it is also useful for th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternal objects like my conscious awareness of <strong>the</strong> tulip.<br />

When we attend to our experiences we use <strong>the</strong><br />

experiences <strong>the</strong>mselves to th<strong>in</strong>k about <strong>the</strong>m. The crucial<br />

feature of phenomenal concepts is that <strong>the</strong>y will always<br />

deploy an <strong>in</strong>stance of <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>the</strong>y are about.<br />

That is, <strong>the</strong>y use <strong>the</strong> denoted experiences <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

mention <strong>the</strong>m. Pap<strong>in</strong>eau writes:<br />

“This means that any exercise of a phenomenal<br />

concept to th<strong>in</strong>k about a perceptual experience<br />

will <strong>in</strong>evitably <strong>in</strong>volve ei<strong>the</strong>r that experience itself<br />

or an imag<strong>in</strong>ary recreation of that experience. If<br />

we count imag<strong>in</strong>ary recreations as ‘versions’ of<br />

<strong>the</strong> experience be<strong>in</strong>g imag<strong>in</strong>ed, <strong>the</strong>n we can say<br />

that <strong>the</strong> phenomenal th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about a given experience<br />

will always use a version of that experience<br />

<strong>in</strong> order to mention that experience.”<br />

(Pap<strong>in</strong>eau 2007, 124)<br />

The problem with this view is that it seems to leave no<br />

room for any k<strong>in</strong>d of physical explanation. The phenomenal<br />

property that <strong>the</strong> phenomenal concept is about<br />

is literally a part of <strong>the</strong> concept itself; as such <strong>the</strong> traditional<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction between representation <strong>and</strong> represented<br />

object that made it possible to specify an explanation<br />

<strong>in</strong> terms of causal / historical correlation between<br />

<strong>the</strong> two has been obliterated. It seems that <strong>the</strong> special<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d of cognitive presence that Pap<strong>in</strong>eau’s account provides<br />

must be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> physical presence of <strong>the</strong><br />

experience alone. But does this really count as an explanation<br />

or is this better characterized as a stipulation?<br />

A Critique of <strong>the</strong> Phenomenal Concept Strategy — Daniel Lim<br />

Dualist Illusion<br />

I believe Chalmers’ dilemma is real <strong>and</strong> must be addressed.<br />

But even if a path can be cut between <strong>the</strong><br />

horns of this dilemma it is far from clear that <strong>the</strong> phenomenal<br />

concept strategy has adequately accounted for<br />

(iii). For ease of exposition I will use <strong>the</strong> ‘explanatory<br />

gap’ (Lev<strong>in</strong>e 2001) as an <strong>in</strong>stance of <strong>the</strong> dualist <strong>in</strong>tuition.<br />

The existence of this gap is someth<strong>in</strong>g defenders of <strong>the</strong><br />

phenomenal concept strategy readily admit. Their claim<br />

is not that <strong>the</strong> gap can be bridged but that its existence<br />

can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed.<br />

Let’s beg<strong>in</strong> by th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about a classic optical<br />

illusion based on human color constancy known as <strong>the</strong><br />

‘checker shadow illusion’. A subject is shown what<br />

appears to be a black <strong>and</strong> white checkerboard with a<br />

cyl<strong>in</strong>der on it that is cast<strong>in</strong>g a diagonal shadow across<br />

<strong>the</strong> middle of <strong>the</strong> board. The squares are actually<br />

different shades of gray <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> image is constructed so<br />

that <strong>the</strong> ‘white’ squares <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> shadow are <strong>the</strong> same<br />

shade as <strong>the</strong> ‘black’ squares outside <strong>the</strong> shadow.<br />

Despite be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> same shade <strong>the</strong> squares appear to be<br />

very different. The st<strong>and</strong>ard explanation for this illusion<br />

has two parts. The first is that our visual system keys <strong>in</strong><br />

on local contrasts – a square that is lighter than its<br />

immediate neighbors is considered ‘lighter than<br />

average’. So <strong>the</strong> mere fact that <strong>the</strong> square <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> shadow<br />

is surrounded by darker squares <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> square outside<br />

<strong>the</strong> shadow is surrounded by lighter squares contributes<br />

to <strong>the</strong> illusion. The second part is that shadows often<br />

have soft edges while pa<strong>in</strong>ted boundaries have hard<br />

edges. Our visual system tends to ignore gradual<br />

changes <strong>in</strong> light<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> order to determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> color of <strong>the</strong><br />

surfaces <strong>in</strong>volved without be<strong>in</strong>g misled by shadows. In<br />

<strong>the</strong> image, <strong>the</strong> cyl<strong>in</strong>der’s shadow is deliberately made<br />

fuzzy to add to this effect.<br />

What we have here is a satisfy<strong>in</strong>g explanation for<br />

<strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong> checker shadow illusion. A vital<br />

feature of this explanation is that it does not presuppose<br />

<strong>the</strong> illusion <strong>in</strong> order to expla<strong>in</strong> it. By expos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

tendencies of our visual system to key <strong>in</strong> on local<br />

contrasts <strong>and</strong> import generic <strong>in</strong>formation concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

boundaries, a non-circular explanation of <strong>the</strong> illusion is<br />

provided. The question is whe<strong>the</strong>r phenomenal concepts<br />

provide such an explanation for <strong>the</strong> explanatory gap.<br />

David Pap<strong>in</strong>eau claims that it does. He locates <strong>the</strong><br />

source of <strong>the</strong> explanatory gap <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence of a use /<br />

mention dist<strong>in</strong>ction regard<strong>in</strong>g phenomenal concepts. The<br />

use / mention dist<strong>in</strong>ction is present <strong>in</strong> a majority of our<br />

nonphenomenal concepts but it is peculiarly absent<br />

when we th<strong>in</strong>k phenomenally. As already gestured at<br />

above, it is <strong>the</strong> way we th<strong>in</strong>k about phenomenal<br />

properties that makes it seem as though we are<br />

apprehend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir essences <strong>and</strong> consequently <strong>in</strong>tuit<strong>in</strong>g<br />

phenomenal properties as ontologically dist<strong>in</strong>ct from<br />

anyth<strong>in</strong>g physical. Phenomenal concepts literally conta<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> properties that <strong>the</strong>y conceptualize so it is no wonder<br />

why we can disassociate <strong>the</strong> physical descriptions of <strong>the</strong><br />

properties from <strong>the</strong> first h<strong>and</strong> experiences of <strong>the</strong><br />

properties <strong>the</strong>mselves. Pap<strong>in</strong>eau writes:<br />

“There is a sense <strong>in</strong> which material concepts do<br />

‘leave out’ <strong>the</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>gs. Uses of <strong>the</strong>m do not <strong>in</strong><br />

any way activate <strong>the</strong> experiences <strong>in</strong> question, by<br />

contrast with uses of phenomenal concepts …<br />

After all, most concepts don’t use or <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>the</strong><br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong>y refer to. When I th<strong>in</strong>k of be<strong>in</strong>g rich,<br />

say, or hav<strong>in</strong>g measles, this doesn’t <strong>in</strong> any sense<br />

make me rich or give me measles.”<br />

(Pap<strong>in</strong>eau 2007, 136)<br />

205

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!