02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The decisive consequences of this account are <strong>the</strong><br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g: phenomenal concepts pick out <strong>the</strong>ir referents<br />

directly <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> all possible worlds – facts which are due to<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal constitution of encapsulation. Importantly,<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> reference of phenomenal concepts is fixed by<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir constitution <strong>and</strong> not by external factors, <strong>the</strong>y carry<br />

essential <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong>ir referents. Tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

Mary-scenario <strong>in</strong>to account it becomes evident that <strong>the</strong><br />

relevant <strong>in</strong>formation has to be about <strong>the</strong> qualitative character<br />

of experiences because it is precisely this sort of <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

<strong>the</strong> scientist lacked <strong>in</strong> her achromatic room <strong>and</strong><br />

ga<strong>in</strong>ed when look<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> sky.<br />

3. Examples of alternative accounts of phenomenal<br />

concepts<br />

In my op<strong>in</strong>ion solely <strong>the</strong> encapsulation relation can expla<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> particularities of phenomenal concepts. Consider, for<br />

example, <strong>the</strong> fact that released Mary ga<strong>in</strong>s a new concept<br />

which importantly carries <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong> very experience<br />

she is undergo<strong>in</strong>g. No demonstrative account of<br />

phenomenal concepts, such as, for example, <strong>the</strong> one developed<br />

by Lev<strong>in</strong> (Lev<strong>in</strong> 2007), can capture this function of<br />

phenomenal concepts. Demonstrative concepts typically<br />

refer to <strong>the</strong> item currently demonstrated at <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

referents differ from one use to ano<strong>the</strong>r. Contrary to this,<br />

my account of phenomenal concepts makes <strong>the</strong>m pick out<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir referent necessarily <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> all possible worlds. Remember,<br />

a phenomenal red-concept should necessarily<br />

carry <strong>in</strong>formation about phenomenal redness to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Mary scenario <strong>and</strong> demonstrative concepts do not meet<br />

this constra<strong>in</strong>t.<br />

If we consider direct recognitional phenomenal concepts<br />

of <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>in</strong>voked by Loar (Loar 1997), we are confronted<br />

with ano<strong>the</strong>r sort of problem: obviously our capacities<br />

to discrim<strong>in</strong>ate experiences outrun our capacities to<br />

recognize experiences. Suppose, Mary has an experience<br />

of <strong>the</strong> shade red21 parallel to shade red23 <strong>and</strong> can discrim<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

<strong>the</strong>se two shades <strong>in</strong>trospectively. Never<strong>the</strong>less,<br />

she may not be able to recognize <strong>the</strong>se shades when she<br />

encounters <strong>the</strong>m. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> recognitional account of<br />

phenomenal concepts Mary has no phenomenal concept<br />

of red21 or red23, although she is attentively experienc<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong>se shades <strong>and</strong> at this moment knows, what it is like to<br />

see <strong>the</strong>m. I take this to be a quite implausible conclusion. 1<br />

These considerations illustrate that no account of<br />

phenomenal concepts which neglects <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>timate l<strong>in</strong>k<br />

between <strong>the</strong>se concepts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir referents can successfully<br />

expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> particularities of <strong>the</strong> concepts Mary acquires<br />

because of her first colour experience. In addition,<br />

accounts which take phenomenal concepts <strong>and</strong> experiences<br />

as separate entities, related to each o<strong>the</strong>r only<br />

causally, face a fur<strong>the</strong>r problem: as Balog (Balog, forthcom<strong>in</strong>g)<br />

po<strong>in</strong>ts out, on such accounts it is conceivable that<br />

a first-person’s application of a phenomenal concept is<br />

performed even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence of <strong>the</strong> experience it refers<br />

to – <strong>and</strong> this is quite an absurd way of treat<strong>in</strong>g phenomenal<br />

concepts. For this reasons, let me return to my <strong>the</strong>sis<br />

of phenomenal concepts encapsulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir referents.<br />

1 My way of argu<strong>in</strong>g shows that I take phenomenal concepts to be s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

concepts apply<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> very occurr<strong>in</strong>g experience. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to my approach,<br />

only a generalization-process on <strong>the</strong> basis of s<strong>in</strong>gular concepts yields<br />

a general phenomenal concept.<br />

Why <strong>the</strong> Phenomenal Concept Strategy Cannot Save Physicalism — Mart<strong>in</strong>a Fürst<br />

4. The dilemma of Pap<strong>in</strong>eaus´s quotational<br />

account of phenomenal concepts<br />

In <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g I want to focus my attention on a physicalist<br />

account, which seems to share <strong>the</strong> here<strong>in</strong> elaborated<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation, but draws physicalistic conclusions from<br />

this: <strong>the</strong> so-called quotational account of phenomenal concepts.<br />

Pap<strong>in</strong>eau developed this account <strong>in</strong> his book Th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g<br />

about consciousness (Pap<strong>in</strong>eau 2002), but changed<br />

some details <strong>in</strong> a recent article (Pap<strong>in</strong>eau 2007).<br />

The quotational account is based on <strong>the</strong> assumption<br />

that phenomenal concepts embed experiences just as<br />

quotation marks embed words. If his analogy is worked out<br />

<strong>in</strong> detail, we will see why Pap<strong>in</strong>eau faces a dilemma: if his<br />

account is understood as a sort of real encapsulation, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

he has to conclude that phenomenal concepts pick out<br />

phenomenal referents. The reasons for this conclusion are<br />

<strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g: if phenomenal concepts are <strong>in</strong>terpreted as<br />

encapsulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir referents, <strong>the</strong>n this unique reference<br />

relation has to be expla<strong>in</strong>ed. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to my analysis,<br />

solely an explanation referr<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> self-present<strong>in</strong>g<br />

character of phenomenal properties <strong>and</strong> our special<br />

acqua<strong>in</strong>tance relation to <strong>the</strong>m can do this explanatory<br />

work. If one wants to avoid this dualistic conclusion, she<br />

has to give a physicalistic account of how a concept can<br />

encapsulate <strong>and</strong> directly refer to a physical item <strong>and</strong> it<br />

seems mysterious how this can be done without <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g<br />

self-present<strong>in</strong>g (phenomenal) properties.<br />

The rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g option is to <strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> quotational<br />

account as phenomenal concepts just us<strong>in</strong>g experiences<br />

without grant<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>y are a logical part of <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

itself. In fact, Pap<strong>in</strong>eau <strong>in</strong> his article “Phenomenal <strong>and</strong><br />

perceptual concepts” (2007) doesn’t seem to believe<br />

anymore that <strong>the</strong> particularities of phenomenal concepts<br />

lie <strong>in</strong> a unique reference relation, but ra<strong>the</strong>r holds that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> special (neuronal) vehicle <strong>in</strong> virtue<br />

of which <strong>the</strong> concept is realized. This suggests that <strong>the</strong><br />

presence of <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept should be<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>ed by a physical (neuronal) presence:<br />

We can helpfully th<strong>in</strong>k of perceptual concepts as <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

stored sensory templates. These templates<br />

will be set up on <strong>in</strong>itial encounters with <strong>the</strong> relevant<br />

referents. They will <strong>the</strong>n be reactivated on later perceptual<br />

encounters. (Pap<strong>in</strong>eau 2007, 114)<br />

Obviously <strong>the</strong> “stored sensory template” has to be understood<br />

as a physical item. At this po<strong>in</strong>t some press<strong>in</strong>g questions<br />

arise: firstly, what is meant by “<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g” <strong>the</strong>se templates?<br />

If this phrase only po<strong>in</strong>ts at simultaneous occurrence<br />

of concept <strong>and</strong> experience, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> concept doesn’t<br />

carry any <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong> qualitative character of <strong>the</strong><br />

experience. If <strong>the</strong> citation has to be understood as a constitutional<br />

relation, one may wonder a) how a physical item<br />

(as a neuronal template) can be encapsulated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

<strong>and</strong> b), how it can carry <strong>the</strong> relevant <strong>in</strong>formation. Ad<br />

a) it can be po<strong>in</strong>ted out that on a physicalist account no<br />

primitive acqua<strong>in</strong>tance relation can be <strong>in</strong>voked to expla<strong>in</strong><br />

this constitution <strong>and</strong> that neural templates are not <strong>in</strong>trospectively<br />

accessible. Next, b) has to be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> more<br />

detail: <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation a phenomenal concept has to carry<br />

surely is not <strong>in</strong>formation about a neural state – o<strong>the</strong>rwise<br />

Mary would have possessed this concept <strong>in</strong> her achromatic<br />

environment. A phenomenal concept has to carry<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong> qualitative character of <strong>the</strong> experience<br />

<strong>and</strong> it is unclear how a physically understood template<br />

can do this, without recurr<strong>in</strong>g to phenomenal properties.<br />

A purely physical description of a (neuronal) template<br />

would obviously leave out precisely <strong>the</strong> sort of <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

a phenomenal concept has to carry to expla<strong>in</strong> Mary’s situa-<br />

107

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!