02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

ord<strong>in</strong>ative, conventional actions—on part of <strong>the</strong> members<br />

of <strong>the</strong> community.<br />

2. Precedent <strong>and</strong> justification<br />

Although my <strong>in</strong>terpretation of §224 surely appears contentious<br />

to many, it should become clear by <strong>the</strong> end of this<br />

section that <strong>in</strong> fact it jibes with <strong>the</strong> traditional read<strong>in</strong>g. I f<strong>in</strong>d<br />

<strong>in</strong> §241 <strong>the</strong> cue to <strong>the</strong> traditional <strong>in</strong>terpretation of “agreement”<br />

<strong>in</strong> §224:<br />

326<br />

Rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g as Coord<strong>in</strong>ation: A Game-<strong>the</strong>oretic Approach — Giacomo Sillari<br />

[Human be<strong>in</strong>gs] agree <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language <strong>the</strong>y use.<br />

That is not agreement <strong>in</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ions but <strong>in</strong> form of life.<br />

Lebensform is a rich <strong>and</strong> profound philosophical concept<br />

that does not reduce to <strong>the</strong> preferences <strong>and</strong> beliefs (to <strong>the</strong><br />

op<strong>in</strong>ions) held <strong>in</strong> a community. Still, I claim that <strong>the</strong> notion<br />

of Lebensform is related to <strong>the</strong> Lewisian picture of conventional<br />

behavior <strong>and</strong> that preferences <strong>and</strong> beliefs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

community <strong>in</strong> fact spr<strong>in</strong>g from it.<br />

Precedent lies at bedrock, where <strong>the</strong> spade is<br />

turned (§ 217) <strong>and</strong> one acts bl<strong>in</strong>dly (§ 219) conform<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

<strong>the</strong> convention <strong>and</strong> obey<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> rule. Without reliance on<br />

precedent, no conventional strategic <strong>in</strong>teraction <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

sense of Lewis is possible <strong>and</strong>, as I have argued <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

previous section, without strategic <strong>in</strong>teraction <strong>the</strong><br />

community is <strong>in</strong> no better position than <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual is <strong>in</strong><br />

determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g which course of action is <strong>in</strong> accord with <strong>the</strong><br />

rule. Indeed, as Margaret Gilbert tersely po<strong>in</strong>ts out <strong>in</strong><br />

(Gilbert 1990), <strong>in</strong> Lewis’s account of convention practical<br />

rationality does not yield any justification to act <strong>in</strong><br />

conformity to precedent. She argues that, on <strong>the</strong> contrary,<br />

conformative action is bl<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>ean sense.<br />

Consider <strong>the</strong> two person case: Given <strong>the</strong>ir conditional<br />

preference, one is justified <strong>in</strong> conform<strong>in</strong>g if she believes<br />

that <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r will conform. But <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r will be justified <strong>in</strong><br />

conform<strong>in</strong>g if he believes that <strong>the</strong> first <strong>in</strong>dividual will. Thus,<br />

she will be justified if she believes that he believes that she<br />

will, <strong>and</strong> so on. In <strong>the</strong> endless replication of each o<strong>the</strong>r’s<br />

reason<strong>in</strong>g, at no po<strong>in</strong>t anyone will come to have sufficient<br />

reason to conform.<br />

I have argued elsewhere (Sillari 2005, 2008) that <strong>in</strong><br />

fact precedent gives rise to <strong>the</strong> series of replications about<br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>tical future conformity, which, <strong>in</strong> turn, <strong>in</strong>ductively<br />

ground for both <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>the</strong> first-order belief that <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r will conform. There is no deductive, <strong>in</strong>fallible<br />

passage from past to future conformity. There ra<strong>the</strong>r is a<br />

causal, <strong>in</strong>ductive one (cf. <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terlocutor <strong>in</strong> §198: “[…]<br />

What sort of connexion is <strong>the</strong>re [between <strong>the</strong> expression of<br />

a rule <strong>and</strong> my actions]?—Well perhaps this one: I have<br />

been tra<strong>in</strong>ed to react to this sign <strong>in</strong> a particular way, <strong>and</strong><br />

now I do so react to it.[—]But that is only to give a causal<br />

connexion […]”) Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> speaks of “bl<strong>in</strong>d action”,<br />

Gilbert speaks of an “a-rational tendency”. For (McDowell<br />

1984), underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g is “precarious <strong>and</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>gent”, <strong>in</strong><br />

that <strong>the</strong>re is no guarantee that my grasp<strong>in</strong>g a concept will<br />

cont<strong>in</strong>ue work<strong>in</strong>g tomorrow as well. No strong, logical,<br />

deductive nexus is to be found between precedent <strong>and</strong><br />

future conformity. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> relation between precedent<br />

<strong>and</strong> future conformity lies at bedrock, as po<strong>in</strong>ted out <strong>in</strong><br />

§481:<br />

If anyone said that <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong> past could<br />

not conv<strong>in</strong>ce him that someth<strong>in</strong>g would happen <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> future, I should not underst<strong>and</strong> him. […] If <strong>the</strong>se<br />

are not grounds, <strong>the</strong>n what are grounds?<br />

As flimsy as <strong>the</strong> relation might be, we all endorse it s<strong>in</strong>ce,<br />

as <strong>the</strong> traditional <strong>in</strong>terpretation of §224 <strong>in</strong>dicates, we all<br />

share an agreement <strong>in</strong> Lebensform. Our systems of con-<br />

cordant beliefs about each o<strong>the</strong>r conformity stem (albeit<br />

not deductively) from such a fundamental agreement. In<br />

turn, from our concordant beliefs <strong>and</strong> conditional preferences<br />

stem our conventions <strong>and</strong> customs, <strong>and</strong> hence our<br />

capacity to obey or to go aga<strong>in</strong>st a rule.<br />

The game-<strong>the</strong>oretic analysis of rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

reveals that preferences <strong>and</strong> beliefs of community<br />

members strategically determ<strong>in</strong>e what course of action is<br />

<strong>in</strong> accord with <strong>the</strong> rule. The formation of beliefs, however,<br />

is a bedrock notion. Can a game-<strong>the</strong>oretic analysis help us<br />

reduce <strong>the</strong> phenomenon of rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g any fur<strong>the</strong>r? It is<br />

well known that Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>vites us not to dig under<br />

bedrock. To ask whe<strong>the</strong>r it is possible, <strong>and</strong> how it may be<br />

done, I f<strong>in</strong>ally tackle <strong>the</strong> issue of <strong>the</strong> relation between<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> turn to <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al section of<br />

this contribution.<br />

3. Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

In this section I focus on mean<strong>in</strong>g by look<strong>in</strong>g at a special<br />

case of coord<strong>in</strong>ation problems <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g communication.<br />

Ra<strong>the</strong>r than attack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> question of mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> language<br />

(a question that lies well beyond <strong>the</strong> scope of this note) I<br />

will look at <strong>the</strong> simpler case of mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> signal<strong>in</strong>g systems<br />

(cf. Lewis 1969). Signal<strong>in</strong>g systems are a special<br />

case of coord<strong>in</strong>ation problems. In a signal<strong>in</strong>g game certa<strong>in</strong><br />

actions (performed by <strong>the</strong> audience) correspond to certa<strong>in</strong><br />

states of <strong>the</strong> world (observed by <strong>the</strong> speaker.) The speaker<br />

sends a signal depend<strong>in</strong>g on what state of <strong>the</strong> world she<br />

observes. The audience performs a certa<strong>in</strong> action depend<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on what signal she receives. Both speaker <strong>and</strong> audience<br />

prefer that <strong>the</strong> action correspond<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> actual<br />

state of <strong>the</strong> world be performed. For that to happen, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

need to coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong>ir strategies (which for <strong>the</strong> speaker<br />

are functions l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g states to signals for <strong>the</strong> speaker, while<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are functions l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g signals to actions for <strong>the</strong> audience.)<br />

When coord<strong>in</strong>ation is achieved, <strong>the</strong>n, a signal may<br />

assume <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicative mean<strong>in</strong>g that “<strong>the</strong> state of <strong>the</strong> world<br />

is such-<strong>and</strong>-such” or <strong>the</strong> imperative mean<strong>in</strong>g “perform<br />

such-<strong>and</strong>-such action!” depend<strong>in</strong>g on fur<strong>the</strong>r characteristics<br />

of <strong>the</strong> situation that need not concern us here. The<br />

relevant po<strong>in</strong>t is that signal<strong>in</strong>g problems are a special k<strong>in</strong>d<br />

of coord<strong>in</strong>ation problems.<br />

The builder-assistant language-game of §2 is a<br />

clear example of a signal<strong>in</strong>g game that one surmises<br />

Lewis might have had it <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when characteriz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

class of signal<strong>in</strong>g games: The builder is <strong>the</strong> speaker. She<br />

observes, for <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>the</strong> state of <strong>the</strong> world <strong>in</strong> which she<br />

needs a slab <strong>and</strong> she sends <strong>the</strong> signal “Slab!”. The<br />

assistant is <strong>the</strong> audience. He receives, <strong>in</strong> this example, <strong>the</strong><br />

signal “Slab!” <strong>and</strong> performs <strong>the</strong> action of br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g a slab.<br />

The caveat issued <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> open<strong>in</strong>g section of this paper can<br />

now be lifted. If rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g is conventional action, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g, as <strong>the</strong> by-product of conventional action<br />

(signal<strong>in</strong>g) is a special case of rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> case of l<strong>in</strong>guistic coord<strong>in</strong>ation, <strong>the</strong> skeptical<br />

paradox can be understood as an <strong>in</strong>stance of <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

of <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acy of mean<strong>in</strong>g. David Lewis, <strong>in</strong> Convention<br />

(cf. pp.199-200) as well as <strong>in</strong> later works, has tackled <strong>the</strong><br />

problem. In particular, <strong>in</strong> (Lewis 1992) he confronts<br />

“Kripkenste<strong>in</strong>’s challenge (formerly Goodman’s challenge)”<br />

(p. 109) <strong>and</strong> argues that for sentences never uttered<br />

before, <strong>the</strong> rules govern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> used fragment of <strong>the</strong><br />

language determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> rules for <strong>the</strong> unused portion, too.<br />

The argument is that <strong>the</strong>y do so because although<br />

extrapolation from used fragment to unused portion is<br />

“radically underdeterm<strong>in</strong>ed”, only a m<strong>in</strong>ority of<br />

extrapolations are straight—<strong>and</strong> acceptable—while <strong>the</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!