02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

A somewhat Elim<strong>in</strong>ativist Proposal about Phenomenal<br />

Consciousness<br />

Pär Sundström, Umeå, Sweden<br />

1. Introduction<br />

Let elim<strong>in</strong>ativism about an object, x, or property, X, be <strong>the</strong><br />

claim that x doesn't exist or X is not <strong>in</strong>stantiated. A<strong>the</strong>ists<br />

are <strong>in</strong> this sense elim<strong>in</strong>ativists about all gods, Christians<br />

are elim<strong>in</strong>ativists about Zeus. More universally, we tend<br />

<strong>the</strong>se days to be elim<strong>in</strong>ativists about impetus, caloric <strong>and</strong><br />

phlogiston.<br />

One may wonder how global <strong>the</strong> threat of<br />

elim<strong>in</strong>ation is. Among <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>and</strong> properties that we<br />

take to exist or be <strong>in</strong>stantiated today, which ones may be<br />

up for "elim<strong>in</strong>ation" tomorrow? This paper focuses on <strong>the</strong><br />

case of phenomenal consciousness, or "what it is like" to<br />

be <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> mental states.<br />

It is often claimed that consciousness is secure<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st elim<strong>in</strong>ation. Flanagan, for example, urges that<br />

consciousness differs importantly from objects <strong>and</strong><br />

properties that have been "elim<strong>in</strong>ated" <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> past.<br />

Phlogiston was hypo<strong>the</strong>sised to exist because it could<br />

expla<strong>in</strong> phenomena that are more immediately present to<br />

us, like burn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> rust<strong>in</strong>g. But consciousness is not, or<br />

not only, assumed to exist because it expla<strong>in</strong>s o<strong>the</strong>r, more<br />

immediately observable phenomena. Consciousness is<br />

also, <strong>and</strong> perhaps primarily, assumed to exist because it is<br />

itself immediately present to us. As Flanagan puts it:<br />

"consciousness as a phenomenon to be expla<strong>in</strong>ed has a<br />

secure place at <strong>the</strong> observational periphery" (1992, 33; cf.<br />

also Chalmers 1996, 102).<br />

It's easy to feel <strong>the</strong> force of Flanagan's suggestion.<br />

However, I shall try to cast some doubt on it <strong>in</strong> what<br />

follows.<br />

Section 2 makes some prelim<strong>in</strong>ary remarks about<br />

"elim<strong>in</strong>ativist" <strong>and</strong> "revisionist" outcomes of <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

developments. Section 3 develops <strong>the</strong> somewhat<br />

elim<strong>in</strong>ativist proposal about phenomenal consciousness.<br />

Section 4 elaborates on <strong>the</strong> elim<strong>in</strong>ativist character of <strong>the</strong><br />

proposal. Section 5 comments on <strong>the</strong> relation between <strong>the</strong><br />

proposal <strong>and</strong> "monitor <strong>the</strong>ories" of consciousness.<br />

2. Elim<strong>in</strong>ativist <strong>and</strong> revisionist conclusions<br />

Every now <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n, we realise that th<strong>in</strong>gs are not quite<br />

<strong>the</strong> way we once thought <strong>the</strong>y were. Noth<strong>in</strong>g is quite <strong>the</strong><br />

way Newtonians thought that mass were. The element<br />

centrally <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> burn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> rust<strong>in</strong>g is not <strong>the</strong> way<br />

phlogiston was taken to be. The heat of a body is not what<br />

caloric <strong>the</strong>orists thought it was. Royalties don't exercise<br />

power with a div<strong>in</strong>e m<strong>and</strong>ate, <strong>and</strong> solidity is not a matter of<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g dense all over.<br />

In some cases where we realise that th<strong>in</strong>gs aren't<br />

<strong>the</strong> way we thought <strong>the</strong>y were, we end up say<strong>in</strong>g<br />

elim<strong>in</strong>ativist th<strong>in</strong>gs like, "<strong>the</strong>re is no x". In o<strong>the</strong>r cases, we<br />

end up say<strong>in</strong>g revisionist th<strong>in</strong>gs like, "x is not quite what<br />

we thought it was".<br />

What determ<strong>in</strong>es whe<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>in</strong> a given case, we end<br />

up say<strong>in</strong>g one th<strong>in</strong>g or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r? Presumably <strong>the</strong><br />

magnitude of our change of view – however exactly that<br />

should be measured – plays some role. If our views on a<br />

340<br />

topic change (by some measure) to a significant extent, we<br />

are presumably more <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to draw an elim<strong>in</strong>ativist<br />

conclusion than if <strong>the</strong>y revised to a lesser extent. But it's<br />

possible that more "pragmatic" factors play a role as well,<br />

for example, whe<strong>the</strong>r researchers judge that <strong>the</strong>y will make<br />

a greater impact by us<strong>in</strong>g one or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r k<strong>in</strong>d of<br />

formulation (c.f. Churchl<strong>and</strong> 1986, 283-4; <strong>and</strong> Stich 1996,<br />

chapter 1).<br />

However that may be, it seems to me that, whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

<strong>in</strong> a given case we end up talk<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> an elim<strong>in</strong>ativist or a<br />

revisionist way is not as such of any <strong>in</strong>terest. What is of<br />

<strong>in</strong>terest is our change of view, <strong>and</strong> I suggest that we can<br />

achieve at least an <strong>in</strong>tuitive sense of how significant such<br />

a change is that is <strong>in</strong>dependent of how we end up<br />

speak<strong>in</strong>g. For example, if Lavoisier had conv<strong>in</strong>ced us to<br />

say th<strong>in</strong>gs like, "phlogiston exists but it's not what we<br />

thought it was", I suggest that we could have achieved <strong>the</strong><br />

same appreciation of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical change that he<br />

contributed to br<strong>in</strong>g about.<br />

I shall next develop a proposal concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

consciousness. Whe<strong>the</strong>r accept<strong>in</strong>g this proposal would<br />

lead us to make elim<strong>in</strong>ativist or revisionist claims, I believe<br />

that, if one comes from a certa<strong>in</strong> natural <strong>and</strong> commonly<br />

occupied start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t, it would amount to a significant<br />

change of view.<br />

3. A proposal about phenomenal consciousness<br />

I shall develop my proposal <strong>in</strong> three steps.<br />

Step 1: Sift<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>the</strong> "Galilean qualities". Consider<br />

a visual experience of a ripe lemon <strong>in</strong> good lightn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

condition. Salient <strong>in</strong> this experience is a certa<strong>in</strong> yellowish<br />

quality. It's somewhat tricky to make this quality a jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

topic of conversation, because <strong>the</strong>re are so many<br />

disagreements about it. For example, while naïve realists<br />

take it to be a property of lemons, sense-datum <strong>the</strong>orists to<br />

be a property of sense-data, some qualia <strong>the</strong>orists may<br />

take it to be a property of conscious experiences, <strong>and</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs take it to not be <strong>in</strong>stantiated at all. There is also<br />

disagreement about how we talk, should talk, <strong>and</strong> can talk<br />

about this quality. Some f<strong>in</strong>d it natural to use <strong>the</strong> term<br />

"yellow" to talk about it, but o<strong>the</strong>rs th<strong>in</strong>k that we don't have<br />

a public language term for it, <strong>and</strong> even that we can't<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduce such a term (Thau 2002, section 5.13).<br />

But despite <strong>the</strong>se obstacles, I th<strong>in</strong>k we can make<br />

this k<strong>in</strong>d of quality a jo<strong>in</strong>t topic of conversation. Whatever<br />

<strong>in</strong>stantiates it, <strong>and</strong> whatever it can <strong>and</strong> should be called, it<br />

is <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d of quality that is most salient <strong>in</strong> our colour<br />

experiences. I will suppose that we have a shared<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g of which type of quality this is.<br />

I will call <strong>the</strong>se qualities "Galilean", s<strong>in</strong>ce I take it to<br />

be <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d of quality that Galileo was concerned with<br />

when he discussed what qualities belong to <strong>the</strong> world <strong>and</strong><br />

what qualities belong to <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d. (I shall later dist<strong>in</strong>guish<br />

<strong>the</strong>se from alleged qualities of ano<strong>the</strong>r type.) I use<br />

"Galilean quality" broadly, for qualities that are salient <strong>in</strong><br />

various sense perceptions like sight, smell <strong>and</strong> taste, <strong>and</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!