02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

272<br />

Reth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Modal Argument aga<strong>in</strong>st Nom<strong>in</strong>al Description Theory — Jiří Raclavský<br />

a code, L, from that understood <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense of a mapp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from possible worlds <strong>and</strong> times to codes, sign it “L”.<br />

Lt me state a semantical scheme I presuppose. An<br />

expression E expresses <strong>in</strong> L a mean<strong>in</strong>g C which<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>es <strong>the</strong> denotatum D of E <strong>in</strong> L. The denotatum of E<br />

<strong>in</strong> L is an <strong>in</strong>tension / a non-<strong>in</strong>tension / noth<strong>in</strong>g. I believe<br />

that <strong>the</strong> adoption of an ‘hyper<strong>in</strong>tensional’ level is<br />

reasonable, differentiat<strong>in</strong>g thus ‘structured mean<strong>in</strong>gs’ from<br />

unstructured denotata. 4 But s<strong>in</strong>ce I will suppress this<br />

semantical consideration <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> present paper, <strong>the</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs of expressions will be identified with <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

denotata. Non-empirical expressions – e.g. genu<strong>in</strong>e proper<br />

names of <strong>in</strong>dividuals, names (or descriptions) of numbers<br />

or ma<strong>the</strong>matical/logical functions – are expressions whose<br />

reference is stable across <strong>the</strong> possible worlds <strong>and</strong> times.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, a typical empirical expression has<br />

a stable denotation but a vary<strong>in</strong>g reference. For <strong>in</strong>stance,<br />

<strong>the</strong> word ‘horse’ denotes a property but it refers to various<br />

classes of <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct worlds <strong>and</strong> times. The<br />

reference of an empirical expression E is <strong>the</strong> value of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>tension denoted by E <strong>in</strong> a particular possible world W,<br />

time-moment T. Examples of empirical expressions: ‘<strong>the</strong><br />

U.S. president’ (which denotes an ‘<strong>in</strong>dividual concept’ but it<br />

refers <strong>in</strong> some W’s, T’s to G.W. Bush, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r W’s, T’s to<br />

J. Ratz<strong>in</strong>ger), ‘It ra<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> Austria’. To know <strong>the</strong> reference of<br />

a typical empirical expression <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> actual world <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

present time one has to exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>gent state of<br />

reality; it is not deducible by means of pure logic. On <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, to know <strong>the</strong> reference of a non-empirical<br />

expression is <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple an a priori matter. Note also that<br />

<strong>the</strong> name relation is best identified with <strong>the</strong> denotation<br />

relation, not with <strong>the</strong> reference relation. For <strong>in</strong>stance, ‘G.W.<br />

Bush’ names what it denotes, i.e. G.W. Bush; ‘<strong>the</strong> U.S.<br />

president’ names certa<strong>in</strong> denoted <strong>in</strong>dividual concept (it is<br />

quite futile to <strong>in</strong>sist on its nam<strong>in</strong>g G.W. Bush).<br />

Ref<strong>in</strong>ements for MA<br />

I have to elucidate some very important dist<strong>in</strong>ctions Kripke<br />

took for granted. One of <strong>the</strong> simplest is concerned with <strong>the</strong><br />

rigidity or non-rigidity <strong>and</strong> expressions. An expression is<br />

rigid iff its reference is stable across possible worlds <strong>and</strong><br />

times; o<strong>the</strong>rwise it is non-rigid. But s<strong>in</strong>ce rigidity is a semantical<br />

property of expressions, it is language-relative.<br />

For <strong>in</strong>stance, when ‘<strong>the</strong> U.S. president’ denotes <strong>in</strong> L' <strong>the</strong><br />

number 7, it is a rigid designator, despite it is a non-rigid<br />

designator <strong>in</strong> L. Correct<strong>in</strong>g thus <strong>the</strong> above def<strong>in</strong>ition: an<br />

expression is rigid <strong>in</strong> L iff its reference <strong>in</strong> L is stable across<br />

<strong>the</strong> possible worlds <strong>and</strong> times. (A variant of this def<strong>in</strong>ition<br />

has “L” <strong>in</strong>stead of both occurrences of L.)<br />

When discuss<strong>in</strong>g semantical properties of<br />

expressions <strong>in</strong> L, Kripke has <strong>in</strong> fact used ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

language, call it M. Assume that <strong>the</strong> code M is a language<br />

of our considerations too. (M works as a certa<strong>in</strong> metalanguage<br />

<strong>in</strong> which we grasp L.) As I have discussed<br />

above, L is underlaid by a specific <strong>in</strong>tensional ground, IGL.<br />

Also M is underlaid by a specific <strong>in</strong>tensional ground, IGM.<br />

With<strong>in</strong> IGM, <strong>the</strong>re is a conceivable circumstance that S<br />

speaks <strong>in</strong> Wk, Tk by means of L, whereas <strong>the</strong>re is also a<br />

th<strong>in</strong>kable circumstance that S enjoys ra<strong>the</strong>r L' <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same<br />

Wk but at Tk+1, or a circumstance that S uses L also <strong>in</strong> Wk'<br />

at Tk+1. Remember, <strong>the</strong>refore, that M is underlaid by a<br />

4 Nearly all ideas from <strong>the</strong> present section are adapted from <strong>the</strong> work of Pavel<br />

Tichý (e.g., 1988). As structured mean<strong>in</strong>gs, Tichý <strong>in</strong>troduced so-called constructions<br />

− abstract (structured) procedures that may be seen as objectual<br />

pendants of λ-terms.<br />

specific IGM which enables us to discuss various<br />

cont<strong>in</strong>gencies, e.g. those about <strong>the</strong> uses of L.<br />

It is quite clear that a genu<strong>in</strong>e proper name such as<br />

N is a rigid designator (of L). Thus <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual N −<br />

named <strong>in</strong> L by N − figures <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensional ground IGL.<br />

However, not every proper name syntactically possible<br />

with<strong>in</strong> L names a particular <strong>in</strong>dividual. For <strong>the</strong> reasons of<br />

simplicity I will assume that a proper name not nam<strong>in</strong>g an<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong> L is mean<strong>in</strong>gless <strong>in</strong> L; it may be also spoken<br />

as a non-designator of L. For <strong>in</strong>stance, an <strong>in</strong>dividual N'<br />

cannot be directly referred to by a proper name N' of L<br />

when N' was not endowed <strong>in</strong> L by a mean<strong>in</strong>g (denotation).<br />

Now when users of L encounter N', <strong>the</strong>y can baptize it by<br />

<strong>the</strong> expression N'. After <strong>the</strong> successful baptism, <strong>the</strong> users<br />

of L cease to use L <strong>in</strong> which N' is mean<strong>in</strong>gless − <strong>the</strong>y<br />

beg<strong>in</strong> to use L' <strong>in</strong> which N' is a genu<strong>in</strong>e proper name.<br />

Needless to say, N' is a rigid designator of L', thus <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual N' figures <strong>in</strong> IGL'. The changes of codes are not<br />

usually noticeable because we do not name codes by L or<br />

L'; we use ra<strong>the</strong>r “L”, i.e. a description s<strong>in</strong>gl<strong>in</strong>g out<br />

particular codes. Briefly, a baptism of an <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

amounts to <strong>the</strong> replacement of L by L' <strong>in</strong> Wk with<strong>in</strong> one<br />

time-<strong>in</strong>terval, a passage from Tk to Tk+1. The description “L”<br />

picks out L <strong>in</strong> Wk, Tk but it picks out L' <strong>in</strong> Wk, Tk+1. N' is a<br />

non-designator of L but it is a rigid designator of L'. 5<br />

A baptism is a cont<strong>in</strong>gent matter figur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>side IGM; when<br />

users of (a value of) “L” baptize certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals, “L”<br />

changes its value – L is replaced by L'.<br />

Now we are ready to dist<strong>in</strong>guish two k<strong>in</strong>ds of<br />

nom<strong>in</strong>al descriptions. The description NDL (or NDL'), i.e.<br />

‘<strong>the</strong> only <strong>in</strong>dividual named <strong>in</strong> L by N', is a rigid nom<strong>in</strong>al<br />

description denot<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>tension which picks out <strong>the</strong> very<br />

same <strong>in</strong>dividual N <strong>in</strong> all possible worlds <strong>and</strong> times. The<br />

relation “named” mentioned <strong>in</strong> it l<strong>in</strong>ks an <strong>in</strong>dividual with N<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> code L. To know which <strong>in</strong>dividual is picked out by<br />

NDL one need not exam<strong>in</strong>e worlds <strong>and</strong> check time – it is<br />

sufficient to f<strong>in</strong>d out which <strong>in</strong>dividual is named <strong>in</strong> L by N. 6<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> description ND“L”, i.e. ‘<strong>the</strong> only <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

named N <strong>in</strong> “L” ’, is (typically) a non-rigid nom<strong>in</strong>al<br />

description denot<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>tension (an <strong>in</strong>dividual concept)<br />

which is not constant. The relation “named” l<strong>in</strong>ks an<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual with N <strong>and</strong> a code which is a cont<strong>in</strong>gent value of<br />

“L”. When <strong>the</strong> value of “L” such as L' conta<strong>in</strong>s N as<br />

a mean<strong>in</strong>gful proper name of N, <strong>the</strong>n ND“L” picks out N.<br />

When <strong>the</strong> value of “L” such as L does not conta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

proper name N as mean<strong>in</strong>gful, <strong>the</strong>n ND“L” picks out<br />

noth<strong>in</strong>g. When <strong>the</strong> value of “L” is L’’, <strong>in</strong> which N means<br />

hors<strong>in</strong>ess, <strong>the</strong>n ND“L” picks out noth<strong>in</strong>g because no<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual is identical with hors<strong>in</strong>ess. Notice also that <strong>the</strong><br />

above disputed circumstances belong to IGM <strong>and</strong> that NDL<br />

<strong>and</strong> ND“L” are mean<strong>in</strong>gful parts of M (not of L or any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

value of “L”).<br />

Soundness of two versions of MA<br />

The orig<strong>in</strong>al MA should be properly ref<strong>in</strong>ed accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

<strong>the</strong> above considerations. There arise <strong>the</strong>reby two versions<br />

of MA: MAL conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g rigid nom<strong>in</strong>al descriptions<br />

<strong>and</strong> MA“L” conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g non-rigid nom<strong>in</strong>al descriptions. It is<br />

easy to conclude that MA“L” is a sound argument. As<br />

NDTians prefer ra<strong>the</strong>r rigid nom<strong>in</strong>al descriptions, <strong>the</strong><br />

5 Note that N' can be a non-rigid designator of L'' or that N − orig<strong>in</strong>ally a rigid<br />

designator of L − can become a non-designator <strong>in</strong> L'', when users of L'' have<br />

forgotten what N meant <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g values of “L”.<br />

6 Rigid nom<strong>in</strong>al descriptions split <strong>in</strong>to two k<strong>in</strong>ds: with or without a reference.<br />

For <strong>in</strong>stance, N'DL refers to no <strong>in</strong>dividual because N' does not name <strong>in</strong> L<br />

anyth<strong>in</strong>g at all. I classify such descriptions as rigid because <strong>the</strong>ir reference<br />

(that is null) is stable, non-vary<strong>in</strong>g.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!