02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Functional Unity of Special Science K<strong>in</strong>ds<br />

Daniel A. Weiskopf, Tampa, Florida, USA<br />

1. <strong>Reduction</strong> vs. elim<strong>in</strong>ation redux<br />

Realization is a relation between a property Φ at one level<br />

of organization <strong>and</strong> a property Ψ or family of properties<br />

Ψ1-Ψn at a lower level of organization. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong><br />

Multiple Realizability (MR) <strong>the</strong>sis, psychological properties,<br />

as well as <strong>the</strong> properties <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong> of many o<strong>the</strong>r special<br />

sciences, are multiply realizable. MR is true of properties<br />

that are def<strong>in</strong>ed by some purpose, capacity, or contribution<br />

<strong>the</strong>y make to some end—generally, by <strong>the</strong>ir functional<br />

role. Where <strong>the</strong>re are <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gly different ways of<br />

play<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> role that def<strong>in</strong>es <strong>the</strong> property Φ, <strong>the</strong>n Φ has<br />

different realizations. For Φ to be multiply realizable, <strong>the</strong><br />

Ψs must belong to dist<strong>in</strong>ct k<strong>in</strong>ds, as def<strong>in</strong>ed by some <strong>in</strong>dependent<br />

taxonomy.<br />

Aga<strong>in</strong>st this consensus, Shapiro (2000) argues that<br />

<strong>the</strong> MR <strong>the</strong>sis is not even coherent. Consider <strong>the</strong> Ψs that<br />

realize Φ. Ei<strong>the</strong>r:<br />

(1) <strong>the</strong>se realizers differ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir causally relevant<br />

properties, or<br />

(2) <strong>the</strong>y do not.<br />

‘Causally relevant properties’ are those that enable<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g hav<strong>in</strong>g Ψ to perform <strong>the</strong> function of a Φ. If (1) is<br />

<strong>the</strong> case, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> Ψs are different k<strong>in</strong>ds. “But if <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

different k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y are not <strong>the</strong> same k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> so we<br />

do not have a case <strong>in</strong> which a s<strong>in</strong>gle k<strong>in</strong>d has multiple<br />

realizations” (Shapiro, 2000, p. 647). That is, if <strong>the</strong> Ψs<br />

possess different causally relevant properties, <strong>the</strong>n Φ itself<br />

does not constitute a k<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>and</strong> hence one higher-level k<strong>in</strong>d<br />

isn’t be<strong>in</strong>g multiply realized. But if (2) is <strong>the</strong> case, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are not different realizations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis is false <strong>in</strong> this<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance.<br />

I agree that if Ψ1 <strong>and</strong> Ψ2 are different <strong>in</strong>dependently<br />

certified k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong>n we have genu<strong>in</strong>e MR. But I deny that<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir be<strong>in</strong>g different k<strong>in</strong>ds entails that Φ is not a k<strong>in</strong>d.<br />

Whe<strong>the</strong>r Φ is a k<strong>in</strong>d or not depends on whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re is a<br />

sufficiently large <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g body of empirical<br />

regularities <strong>in</strong> which Φ itself is implicated. K<strong>in</strong>dhood<br />

depends on <strong>the</strong>re be<strong>in</strong>g a rich cluster of properties that<br />

reliably co-occur with someth<strong>in</strong>g’s be<strong>in</strong>g Φ, where <strong>the</strong>se<br />

properties do not cluster toge<strong>the</strong>r by chance but by <strong>the</strong><br />

operation of some govern<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple or mechanism.<br />

It might seem that if Ψ1 <strong>and</strong> Ψ2 are causally different<br />

ways of br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g about Φ that this would automatically<br />

show that <strong>the</strong>y did not participate <strong>in</strong> any (nonanalytic)<br />

common regularities. But this isn’t obviously true, s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ct mechanisms can still give rise to shared properties<br />

<strong>and</strong> generalizations. We can see this by look<strong>in</strong>g at an<br />

example that Shapiro himself discusses: <strong>the</strong> case of<br />

compound vs. camera eyes.<br />

2. The eyes of o<strong>the</strong>rs<br />

Arthropod compound eyes <strong>and</strong> vertebrate camera eyes<br />

are all eyes <strong>in</strong> virtue of fall<strong>in</strong>g under <strong>the</strong> functional description<br />

‘organs for see<strong>in</strong>g’. But different mechanisms are <strong>in</strong>volved<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> production of sight <strong>in</strong> each k<strong>in</strong>d of eye;<br />

hence, by <strong>the</strong> anti-MR argument, eyes should not be a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle k<strong>in</strong>d. However, both k<strong>in</strong>ds of eyes can display simi-<br />

lar psychophysical phenomena despite hav<strong>in</strong>g different<br />

optical properties.<br />

The ma<strong>in</strong> phenomenon of <strong>in</strong>terest is <strong>the</strong> perception<br />

of Mach b<strong>and</strong>s: regions of especially high or low<br />

brightness that occur at <strong>the</strong> high or low ends of a<br />

brightness gradient. While perception of Mach b<strong>and</strong>s<br />

occurs <strong>in</strong> many organisms, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g primates, cats, <strong>and</strong><br />

horseshoe crabs (Limulus polyphemus), <strong>the</strong> neural circuits<br />

that underlie it differ radically across species. This can be<br />

illustrated with respect to <strong>the</strong> Limulus eye <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

mammalian eye.<br />

The lateral eyes of Limulus are composed of ~1000<br />

cones that term<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>in</strong> ommatidia (Battelle, 2006).<br />

Ommatidia conta<strong>in</strong> photoreceptive cells that depolarize a<br />

central eccentric cell, <strong>the</strong> axons of which form <strong>the</strong> optic<br />

tract. Eccentric cell axons also distribute collaterals to <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

neighbors <strong>in</strong> adjacent ommatidia. These <strong>in</strong>terwoven<br />

branch<strong>in</strong>g collaterals form <strong>the</strong> lateral plexus of <strong>the</strong> eye,<br />

which enables one ommatidium to be <strong>in</strong>hibited by activity<br />

<strong>in</strong> adjacent ones (Hartl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> Ratliff, 1957). Lateral<br />

<strong>in</strong>hibition enhances contrast <strong>and</strong> sharpens perception of<br />

edges, <strong>and</strong> also expla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> perception of Mach b<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

Mammalian eyes, while physically <strong>and</strong> optically<br />

different from compound eyes, also conta<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>hibitory<br />

mechanisms that produce Mach b<strong>and</strong>s. In contrast to <strong>the</strong><br />

loose organization of <strong>the</strong> lateral plexus, mammalian ret<strong>in</strong>as<br />

are tightly organized <strong>in</strong>to dist<strong>in</strong>ct layers. They also use a<br />

vastly greater range of cell types than does <strong>the</strong> Limulus<br />

eye. Photoreceptive cells feed <strong>in</strong>to a network conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

horizontal, amacr<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> bipolar cells, f<strong>in</strong>ally term<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g<br />

at ganglion cells that project to higher regions. While <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are many loci for lateral <strong>in</strong>hibition <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ret<strong>in</strong>a, it occurs<br />

<strong>in</strong>itially <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> horizontal cells l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g adjacent rods <strong>and</strong><br />

cones. These cells have highly specific connectivity<br />

patterns, as opposed to <strong>the</strong> near-r<strong>and</strong>om wir<strong>in</strong>g of Limulus<br />

(Field <strong>and</strong> Chichilnisky, 2007; Sterl<strong>in</strong>g, 1998).<br />

So we have two dist<strong>in</strong>ct mechanisms for produc<strong>in</strong>g<br />

lateral <strong>in</strong>hibition, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore two ways of construct<strong>in</strong>g<br />

visual systems that can perceive Mach b<strong>and</strong>s. Yet both<br />

eyes share more extensive causal properties than just<br />

enabl<strong>in</strong>g sight. Implement<strong>in</strong>g lateral <strong>in</strong>hibition <strong>and</strong><br />

produc<strong>in</strong>g Mach b<strong>and</strong>s are two such <strong>in</strong>terconnected<br />

properties. While <strong>the</strong>se are not exhaustive of <strong>the</strong> possible<br />

k<strong>in</strong>ds of eyes, <strong>the</strong>y illustrate <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t that dist<strong>in</strong>ct k<strong>in</strong>ds at<br />

one level can have numerous o<strong>the</strong>r common causal<br />

properties, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore constitute a higher-level k<strong>in</strong>d.<br />

Thus Shapiro’s <strong>in</strong>ference from different causal properties<br />

to <strong>the</strong> absence of a higher-level k<strong>in</strong>d is not generally<br />

sound. Whe<strong>the</strong>r a functionally def<strong>in</strong>ed property also<br />

constitutes a k<strong>in</strong>d is someth<strong>in</strong>g to be decided on a caseby-case<br />

basis.<br />

3. Unity through constra<strong>in</strong>t?<br />

Interest<strong>in</strong>gly, Shapiro considers <strong>the</strong> case of lateral <strong>in</strong>hibition,<br />

but draws <strong>the</strong> opposite conclusion from it (Shapiro,<br />

2004, pp. 117-120). Ra<strong>the</strong>r than conclud<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> use of<br />

this common strategy of visual process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> different species<br />

shows its multiple realizability, he suggests that it<br />

shows that <strong>the</strong> evolution of visual systems occurs under<br />

tight constra<strong>in</strong>ts. These constra<strong>in</strong>ts mean that <strong>the</strong>re will<br />

387

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!