02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

could <strong>the</strong>n deduce (1c) <strong>and</strong> conclude that S does not know<br />

any ord<strong>in</strong>ary proposition p. In ano<strong>the</strong>r context, different HP<br />

might be taken for granted that are consistent with K(S, p)<br />

but not with some of <strong>the</strong> sceptic’s presuppositions outl<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

above. Then (1) would allow us to <strong>in</strong>fer that S knows <strong>the</strong><br />

denial of <strong>the</strong> sceptical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Note, however, that<br />

even if <strong>the</strong> sceptic relies on certa<strong>in</strong> HP this is not enough<br />

to give a direct argument aga<strong>in</strong>st her. But it is enough to<br />

restrict <strong>the</strong> devastat<strong>in</strong>g impact on our ord<strong>in</strong>ary knowledge<br />

claims to contexts <strong>in</strong> which sceptical HP hold. This is one<br />

way to make sense of <strong>the</strong> conjecture that <strong>the</strong> truth of a<br />

given knowledge claim can vary with context.<br />

A po<strong>in</strong>t that needs more work is avoid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

account to over generate. So far it seems as if any<br />

knowledge claim could be justified, given that certa<strong>in</strong> HP<br />

hold, as absurd as <strong>the</strong>y may be. So we need a mechanism<br />

that i) restricts <strong>the</strong> admissible HP <strong>and</strong> that ii) can bridge<br />

<strong>the</strong> gap between <strong>in</strong>ternal factors like tak<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g for<br />

granted <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> external factors that allow for <strong>the</strong><br />

implication K(S, p) → p, i. e., <strong>the</strong> factivity of knowledge. An<br />

additional externalist conception of justification could solve<br />

both of <strong>the</strong>se problems. Consider, for <strong>the</strong> sake of<br />

illustration, a reliabilist account that <strong>in</strong>corporates <strong>the</strong><br />

methods by which we form our beliefs about certa<strong>in</strong><br />

propositions. This would avoid not only fancyful HP as<br />

<strong>the</strong>se would be analogous to unreliable methods, but also<br />

Gettier cases. It would have <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r merit of allow<strong>in</strong>g for<br />

fallibility, as a method of form<strong>in</strong>g beliefs that we thought<br />

trustworthy might turn out to be false. In <strong>the</strong> spirit of <strong>the</strong><br />

experiment-example <strong>in</strong> § 2: Future <strong>in</strong>vestigation might<br />

reveal that <strong>the</strong> apparatus we used is not as precise as we<br />

took it to be or even that it does not measure what we<br />

thought it did. Even though some of <strong>the</strong> beliefs we based<br />

on <strong>the</strong> data <strong>the</strong> apparatus delivered were <strong>in</strong> fact true, we<br />

would no longer consider <strong>the</strong>m as known due to <strong>the</strong><br />

unreliable process by which we formed our belief <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

However, noth<strong>in</strong>g h<strong>in</strong>ges on this specific epistemological<br />

account. The notion of HP is fairly neutral to o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

externalist suggestions.<br />

4. Conversational mechanisms<br />

The analysis sketched so far did not address <strong>the</strong> conversational<br />

application of different HP. One possibility to systematize<br />

<strong>the</strong> account seems to be <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>corporation of a<br />

Stalnaker-style notion of common ground. The def<strong>in</strong>ition is<br />

as follows:<br />

Scepticism, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>'s H<strong>in</strong>ge Propositions, <strong>and</strong> Common Ground — Erik Stei<br />

“It is common ground that Φ <strong>in</strong> a group if all members<br />

accept (for <strong>the</strong> purpose of <strong>the</strong> conversation)<br />

that Φ, <strong>and</strong> all believe that all accept that Φ, <strong>and</strong> all<br />

believe that all believe that all accept that Φ, etc.”<br />

(Stalnaker 2002: 716)<br />

Acceptance, follow<strong>in</strong>g Stalnaker, is a propositional attitude<br />

as well as a methodological stance toward a proposition.<br />

To accept some proposition Φ is to treat it as true <strong>and</strong> to<br />

“ignore, at least temporarily, <strong>and</strong> perhaps <strong>in</strong> a limited context,<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility that it is false” (Stalnaker 2002: 716).<br />

Apply<strong>in</strong>g this idea to <strong>the</strong> position developed <strong>in</strong> § 3, this<br />

means, roughly, that we accept some proposition Φ as true<br />

<strong>in</strong> a context C1 <strong>in</strong> order to undertake a reasonable <strong>in</strong>vestigation<br />

I1. Given Φ is an essential presupposition <strong>in</strong> C1,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n <strong>in</strong> case we doubt Φ, this shifts <strong>the</strong> context as well as<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigation we are <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> to I2 <strong>in</strong> C2. 4 Thus,<br />

4 Stalnaker does not mention context shifts, but only context changes, that<br />

decrease <strong>the</strong> set of possible worlds under consideration. I dist<strong>in</strong>guish context-<br />

what depends on contextual factors is <strong>the</strong> question which<br />

propositions we are will<strong>in</strong>g to accept as given <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

where to stop <strong>the</strong> regress of justification. The connection I<br />

propose is that HP determ<strong>in</strong>e, at least <strong>in</strong> part, which<br />

propositions we are will<strong>in</strong>g to accept.<br />

In st<strong>and</strong>ard cases, conversational contexts are<br />

dynamic <strong>in</strong> such a way that <strong>the</strong>y are constantly extended<br />

by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>corporation of new <strong>in</strong>formation—this is a central<br />

feature of communication <strong>and</strong> not an <strong>in</strong>stance of context<br />

shifts. It is captured by <strong>the</strong> notion of accommodation,<br />

which can be illustrated by <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g example. Imag<strong>in</strong>e<br />

a conversation between Alice <strong>and</strong> Bob, where Alice utters:<br />

(2) I can’t come to <strong>the</strong> meet<strong>in</strong>g – I have to pick up<br />

my sister at <strong>the</strong> airport.<br />

Given that Alice is a competent speaker of English <strong>and</strong><br />

also that <strong>the</strong> basic pragmatic mechanisms, e. g., a<br />

Gricean-style Cooperative Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>and</strong> some conversational<br />

maxims (Grice 1989), are at work, Bob can <strong>in</strong>fer<br />

from (2) that Alice believes that it is common belief that<br />

she has a sister. The latter now common belief (as Bob<br />

believes it as well after Alice’s utterance of (2)) leads Bob<br />

to belief that Alice has a sister, which makes Alice’s hav<strong>in</strong>g<br />

a sister common belief <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context at issue (cf. Stalnaker<br />

2002: 709-710). If Bob <strong>and</strong> Alice are discuss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> question<br />

who is go<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> meet<strong>in</strong>g next Friday, Alice has<br />

merely <strong>in</strong>troduced a proposition to be <strong>in</strong>tegrated <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong><br />

common ground by decreas<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> set of possible world<br />

compatible with <strong>the</strong> state of <strong>the</strong> conversation. Consider, <strong>in</strong><br />

contrast, <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g dialogue:<br />

(3) a. [Alice]: I can’t come to <strong>the</strong> meet<strong>in</strong>g – I have<br />

to pick up my sister at <strong>the</strong> airport.<br />

b. [Bob]: You can’t pick up your sister at <strong>the</strong><br />

airport. In fact <strong>the</strong>re is no airport, <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

sister, <strong>and</strong> I’m not here ei<strong>the</strong>r. You are a bra<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong> a vat with all your impressions stimulated by<br />

a mad scientist.<br />

In this case, it does not seem as if Bob <strong>in</strong>troduced new<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, his answer (3b) reveals a defective<br />

context. While <strong>in</strong> a nondefective context “<strong>the</strong> participants’<br />

beliefs about <strong>the</strong> common ground are all correct” (Stalnaker<br />

2002: 717), this is not <strong>the</strong> case <strong>in</strong> a defective context.<br />

Before Bob’s utterance of (3b), Alice believed that a<br />

proposition like that <strong>the</strong> external world exists was part of<br />

<strong>the</strong> common ground. Bob’s answer, however, made it<br />

manifest that it was not <strong>and</strong> thus, that <strong>the</strong> context was<br />

defective. Alice now seems to have two options: ei<strong>the</strong>r she<br />

accommodates Bob’s utterance <strong>and</strong> thus accepts <strong>the</strong> shift<br />

to a sceptical context, i. e., she accepts enter<strong>in</strong>g a new<br />

conversation, or she rejects <strong>the</strong> context-shift by refus<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

accommodate (3b). This leads to <strong>the</strong> quite natural result<br />

that <strong>in</strong> case she accepts <strong>the</strong> context-shift, we would not be<br />

<strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to ascribe her knowledge of any ord<strong>in</strong>ary proposition.<br />

If, however, she refuses accommodat<strong>in</strong>g (3b) we are<br />

still will<strong>in</strong>g to ascribe her knowledge of that proposition. I<br />

th<strong>in</strong>k it is <strong>the</strong> latter option that is more likely to be chosen <strong>in</strong><br />

every-day conversation.<br />

shifts as <strong>the</strong> result of a defective context <strong>in</strong> which a given conversational aim<br />

could not be achieved. It is similar to beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g an entirely new conversation.<br />

335

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!