02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

offer a solution to <strong>the</strong> bad company problem) <strong>and</strong> show<br />

that both abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciples satisfy it.<br />

A famous worry for <strong>the</strong> Neo-Fregean project, called<br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘bad company’ problem, relates to <strong>the</strong> fact that not all<br />

abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciples are consistent. A famously<br />

<strong>in</strong>consistent abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is Frege’s notorious<br />

Basic Law V:<br />

Benacerraf <strong>and</strong> Bad Company (An Attack on Neo-Fregeanism) — Michael Gabbay<br />

∀F∀G [ εx.Fx = εx.Gx ↔ ∀x(Fx ↔ Gx) ] (14)<br />

We can use (14) to derive Russell’s paradox. An argument<br />

of Heck [Heck 1992] shows that <strong>the</strong>re are many<br />

undesirable abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. For example, <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

many Φ for which <strong>the</strong> abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciple:<br />

∀F∀G [ εx.Fx = εx.Gx ↔ Φ ∨ ∀x(Fx ↔ Gx) ] (15)<br />

entails that Φ. It is not hard to f<strong>in</strong>d plenty of second order<br />

sentences Φ (some of which conta<strong>in</strong> F <strong>and</strong> G) that are<br />

entailed by an abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciple like (15) which we<br />

would certa<strong>in</strong>ly th<strong>in</strong>k ought not to be true. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,<br />

different abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciples can be <strong>in</strong>compatible with<br />

each o<strong>the</strong>r, although <strong>in</strong>dividually consistent; this is strange,<br />

as abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciples are supposed to be analytic <strong>and</strong><br />

so ought to be true, <strong>and</strong> hence compatible, <strong>in</strong> any context.<br />

There is <strong>the</strong>n a question whe<strong>the</strong>r some pr<strong>in</strong>ciple can be<br />

given to discern <strong>the</strong> acceptable abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciples from<br />

<strong>the</strong> unacceptable ones (see [Weir 2003] for many<br />

examples of unacceptable abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciples). I now<br />

present such a pr<strong>in</strong>ciple.<br />

Let λ be any <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite card<strong>in</strong>al, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> consistency<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>t for λ is <strong>the</strong> condition that any abstraction<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple should have <strong>the</strong> form:<br />

∀F∀G [ εx.Fx = εx.Gx ↔ Ψλ(F, G) ∨ ∀x(Fx ↔ Gx) ] (16)<br />

Where<br />

i. Ψλ(F, G) is a second order sentence conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

no free variables o<strong>the</strong>r than F <strong>and</strong> G, <strong>and</strong> also<br />

does conta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘new’ abstraction operator εx.<br />

ii. Ψλ is a transitive <strong>and</strong> symmetric relation on<br />

unary predicates. That is:<br />

- Ψλ(F, G) implies Ψλ(G, F)<br />

- Ψλ(F, G) <strong>and</strong> Ψλ(G, H) implies Ψλ(F, H)<br />

iii. For any model M of card<strong>in</strong>ality λ, <strong>the</strong>re are at<br />

most λ many valuations σ such that σ(Ψλ(F, G))<br />

= ⊥ . 1<br />

Note that <strong>the</strong> familiar examples of ‘bad’ abstraction<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples (e.g. <strong>in</strong> [Weir 2003]) violate this condition. For<br />

example <strong>in</strong> Frege’s Basic Law V has <strong>the</strong> form<br />

∀F∀G [ εx.Fx = εx.Gx ↔ ⊥ ∨ ∀x(Fx ↔ Gx) ]<br />

which clearly violates this condition for any λ. Note also<br />

that Benacerraf’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>and</strong> Hume’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple satisfy <strong>the</strong><br />

consistency constra<strong>in</strong>t for any <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite λ. 2 Now we can show<br />

that any abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciple satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> consistency<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>t for λ can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> any second order<br />

model of card<strong>in</strong>ality at least λ. Let Mλ be a model (that can<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> language of Ψ) with doma<strong>in</strong> |Mλ| of card<strong>in</strong>ality<br />

λ. Let R be a relation on properties (i.e. a relation on<br />

subsets of |Mλ|) such that<br />

1 This says that <strong>the</strong> (second order) property represented by Ψλ groups <strong>the</strong><br />

properties of <strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>to at most λ many different equivalence classes. In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r words, Ψλ is only allowed to dist<strong>in</strong>guish up to extensionality, all properties<br />

(i.e. subsets of |M| ) of card<strong>in</strong>ality < λ . Ψλ must be unable to dist<strong>in</strong>guish all<br />

but λ of <strong>the</strong> 2λ properties of card<strong>in</strong>ality λ.<br />

2 We must view Hume’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple as: ∀F∀G [ εx.Fx = εx.Gx ↔ F1~1G ∨<br />

∀x(Fx ↔ Gx) ]<br />

R(P, Q) iff σ(Ψλ(F, G)) = T<br />

for any valuation σ such that σ(F) = P <strong>and</strong> σ(G) = Q. 3 In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r words, R is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation of Ψλ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> model Mλ.<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce Ψλ(F, G) conta<strong>in</strong>s no free first or second order<br />

variables o<strong>the</strong>r than F <strong>and</strong> G, R does not depend on σ.<br />

If P ⊆ |Mλ| <strong>the</strong>n let PR = {Q: R(P, Q) or P = Q}.<br />

Clearly, PR is an equivalence class. Now consider <strong>the</strong> set<br />

A = {PR: P ⊆ |Mλ|} <strong>and</strong> let μ be its card<strong>in</strong>ality. If μ > λ, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

<strong>the</strong>re would be more than λ many valuations σ that falsify<br />

Ψλ(F, G) (at least one for each of <strong>the</strong> μ-many pairs of<br />

different equivalence classes <strong>in</strong> A). This would violate<br />

condition (iii) of <strong>the</strong> consistency constra<strong>in</strong>t for λ. So μ ≤ λ,<br />

i.e. <strong>the</strong> card<strong>in</strong>ality of A is less than or equal to <strong>the</strong><br />

card<strong>in</strong>ality of |Mλ|. It follows <strong>the</strong>n, that <strong>the</strong>re is an <strong>in</strong>jection f<br />

from{PR: P ⊆ |Mλ|} <strong>in</strong>to |Mλ|.<br />

We may use f to identify elements eP ∈ |Mλ|:<br />

eP = f(PR) (17)<br />

It is now a straightforward matter to check that<br />

eP = eQ iff R(P, Q) or P = Q<br />

It follows that we can extend any second order model Mλ of<br />

card<strong>in</strong>ality λ, with an abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciple satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

consistency constra<strong>in</strong>t for λ: we def<strong>in</strong>e eP as <strong>in</strong> (17) <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>n extend Mλ to <strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> new language us<strong>in</strong>g (18):<br />

σ(εx.Fx) = e{m: m∈|M λ | <strong>and</strong> σ [x/m] (Fx) = T}<br />

(18)<br />

Let me describe this <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> English: Ψλ forms<br />

equivalence classes of properties; <strong>the</strong> conditions on Ψλ<br />

guarantee that <strong>the</strong>re is a one-one function f from <strong>the</strong>se<br />

equivalence classes <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong> |Mλ| of Mλ; we<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> referent of εx.Fx under valuation σ as <strong>the</strong><br />

element e which <strong>the</strong> function f assigns to <strong>the</strong> equivalence<br />

class of properties that Ψλ forms from <strong>the</strong> extension of F.<br />

We now have <strong>in</strong> (16) a general criterion for <strong>the</strong><br />

legitimacy of abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. This criterion<br />

legitimates Benacerraf’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple as well as Hume’s<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. The only difference between <strong>the</strong>m be<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

extend<strong>in</strong>g a model to validate Benacerraf’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is<br />

slightly more straightforward than Hume’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Say<br />

that an abstraction pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is almost analytic if it satisfies<br />

<strong>the</strong> consistency constra<strong>in</strong>t for any <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite λ. It is now a<br />

matter of dispute whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> fact that λ has to be <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

detracts from <strong>the</strong> analyticity of Hume’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>and</strong><br />

Benacerraf’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. A po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> favour of <strong>the</strong> Neo-<br />

Fregean programme is that we can give an <strong>in</strong>dependently<br />

motivated formal reasons for treat<strong>in</strong>g Hume’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple as<br />

analytic <strong>and</strong> rule out pr<strong>in</strong>ciples like Basic Law V. However,<br />

a po<strong>in</strong>t aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> Neo-Fregean programme is that<br />

Benacerraf’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple also comes out as analytic, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

argument of Section 3.3 st<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

4.2 The concept of number<br />

Perhaps some argument relat<strong>in</strong>g to our concept of number<br />

will differentiate between <strong>the</strong> two pr<strong>in</strong>ciples.<br />

The possibility of any such argument is extremely<br />

doubtful, if anyth<strong>in</strong>g but for <strong>the</strong> fact that nei<strong>the</strong>r Hume’s<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple nor Benacerraf’s pr<strong>in</strong>ciple make good analyses of<br />

our number concepts. Wright acknowledges this:<br />

3 σ assigns elements of Mλ to first order variables <strong>and</strong> subsets of Mλ to second<br />

order variables; σ[x/m] is a valuation that agrees with σ on all variables<br />

except that it maps <strong>the</strong> variable x to m.<br />

111

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!