02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>in</strong>tentional states requires functionally def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stead of someth<strong>in</strong>g else. For surely we need<br />

to be able to differentiate <strong>the</strong> contents of <strong>in</strong>tentional states<br />

<strong>in</strong> order to differentiate <strong>the</strong> states <strong>the</strong>mselves. And if a<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ition does not enable us to tell <strong>the</strong> difference between,<br />

say, believ<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>re is a cow <strong>in</strong> front of me <strong>and</strong> believ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re is a horse <strong>in</strong> front of me, <strong>the</strong>n it is clearly not<br />

adequate to <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> concept of belief. Those<br />

who th<strong>in</strong>k that mental content does not depend on public<br />

language might object that considerations of word mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

do not apply to <strong>in</strong>tentional states. I believe that mental<br />

content does depend on public language. But even if it<br />

does not, <strong>in</strong> order to have reductive explanation, we need<br />

to be able to publicly refer to specific mental contents. So<br />

<strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between different mental contents needs to<br />

be done <strong>in</strong> public language. Thus similar considerations<br />

apply. So let us take a look at Kripke’s argument aga<strong>in</strong>st<br />

dispositional analyses of mean<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Kripke’s ma<strong>in</strong> argument aga<strong>in</strong>st dispositionalism is<br />

<strong>the</strong> normativity argument, which I will now lay out. In order<br />

to make it <strong>the</strong> case that I mean anyth<strong>in</strong>g by a word, <strong>the</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g-determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g fact needs to make <strong>the</strong> difference<br />

between right <strong>and</strong> wrong uses of <strong>the</strong> word. It needs to<br />

justify my us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> word <strong>the</strong> way I use it (if I actually am<br />

us<strong>in</strong>g it correctly). But dispositions can not do this. If what I<br />

mean by a word was determ<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> way I am disposed<br />

to use it, <strong>the</strong>n whatever I say would be correct (Kripke<br />

1982, 24). I could not mistake a cow for a horse, for if I<br />

called a cow ‘horse’, <strong>the</strong>n that particular cow would, for<br />

that very reason, be <strong>in</strong>cluded among <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs I mean by<br />

‘horse’. So <strong>the</strong>re would be no dist<strong>in</strong>ction between us<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

word correctly, <strong>in</strong> accordance with its mean<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g it<br />

<strong>in</strong>correctly. From this it follows that <strong>the</strong>re would be no such<br />

th<strong>in</strong>g as mean<strong>in</strong>g anyth<strong>in</strong>g by a word.<br />

There are, of course, o<strong>the</strong>r c<strong>and</strong>idate solutions for<br />

<strong>the</strong> rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g problem, besides <strong>the</strong> Kripkean<br />

community view <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> simple dispositional view. The<br />

most promis<strong>in</strong>g such solutions will not, however, help <strong>the</strong><br />

case of reductionism, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y do not offer causalfunctional<br />

analyses of mean<strong>in</strong>g. I have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d here<br />

primarily <strong>the</strong> accounts of Crisp<strong>in</strong> Wright <strong>and</strong> Philip Pettit,<br />

which are, <strong>in</strong> essence, versions of <strong>the</strong> community view<br />

(see Kusch 2006, ch. 7). The reductionist needs a solution<br />

close enough to <strong>the</strong> simple dispositional view to yield<br />

functional def<strong>in</strong>itions.<br />

The lesson to be learned from <strong>the</strong> normativity<br />

argument is this: Mean<strong>in</strong>g is normative. In order for a word<br />

to mean someth<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>re must be correct <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>correct<br />

ways to use <strong>the</strong> word. Any functional def<strong>in</strong>ition of mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

must ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> this dist<strong>in</strong>ction between correctness <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>correctness. Similarly, any functional def<strong>in</strong>ition of<br />

<strong>in</strong>tentional states must ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between fit<br />

<strong>and</strong> misfit with actual states of affairs (<strong>in</strong> case of belief this<br />

amounts to <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between true <strong>and</strong> false beliefs,<br />

<strong>in</strong> case of desires, satisfied <strong>and</strong> not satisfied desires, <strong>and</strong><br />

so on). Next I will take a brief look at some causalfunctional<br />

analyses of <strong>in</strong>tentional states, <strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong><br />

normativity argument shows <strong>the</strong>m to be defective.<br />

3. Functional Analyses of Intentional States<br />

The first functional analysis I will consider is W.V.O.<br />

Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s behavioural semantics (Qu<strong>in</strong>e 1960). Qu<strong>in</strong>e, of<br />

course, <strong>in</strong>tended his analysis to be an analysis of <strong>the</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g of sentences, for he did not believe <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional<br />

states (see Qu<strong>in</strong>e 1960, 221). It is, however, quite straightforward<br />

to extend <strong>the</strong> behavioural account also to mental<br />

content. Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s basic idea was that <strong>the</strong> (stimulus) mean-<br />

Rule-Follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Irreducibility of Intentional States — Antti Heik<strong>in</strong>heimo<br />

<strong>in</strong>g of a sentence is <strong>the</strong> set of stimuli, presented with which<br />

a language user would, if queried, affirm <strong>the</strong> sentence <strong>in</strong><br />

question (Qu<strong>in</strong>e 1960, 32). So it is natural to say that <strong>the</strong><br />

same set of stimuli constitutes <strong>the</strong> content of a belief of <strong>the</strong><br />

language user. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, that he/she believes <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence to be true. Functional def<strong>in</strong>itions of o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>tentional<br />

states along <strong>the</strong>se l<strong>in</strong>es may be more complicated,<br />

but it does not matter to my argument. If <strong>the</strong> behavioural<br />

account fails <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of belief, which is <strong>the</strong> simplest<br />

case, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re is not much hope for it <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r cases<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r. Now it is easily seen that <strong>the</strong> normativity argument<br />

refutes <strong>the</strong> behavioural account. For <strong>the</strong> behavioural account<br />

is really noth<strong>in</strong>g more than <strong>the</strong> simple dispositional<br />

account already discussed. If whatever stimulus that<br />

prompts me to affirm a sentence is counted as partly determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> sentence, <strong>the</strong>n it is not possible<br />

for me to make a mistake by affirm<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> sentence.<br />

So <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of belief, all my beliefs will be true, for <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

contents are determ<strong>in</strong>ed by whatever <strong>the</strong> facts happen to<br />

be when I express <strong>the</strong> beliefs. Qu<strong>in</strong>e, of course, tried to<br />

make room for mistakes, but even he had to acknowledge<br />

that from <strong>the</strong> behavioural account follow all k<strong>in</strong>ds of <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acy<br />

<strong>in</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g, so that it would often have to be<br />

more or less arbitrarily decided whe<strong>the</strong>r someone is mistaken<br />

or uses a word <strong>in</strong> an unusual way.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r possible source for functional def<strong>in</strong>itions is<br />

a sentences-<strong>in</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-head view. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to such a view,<br />

<strong>in</strong>tentional states are bra<strong>in</strong> states that somehow resemble<br />

public language sentences. The most important example<br />

of such a view is Jerry Fodor’s language of thought -<br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (Fodor 1976). There are at least two possible<br />

ways to conceive of sentences <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> head. They could<br />

have content <strong>in</strong> virtue of <strong>the</strong>ir non-causal properties, such<br />

as some k<strong>in</strong>d of isomorphism with public language<br />

sentences. Or <strong>the</strong>y could have content <strong>in</strong> virtue of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

role <strong>in</strong> controll<strong>in</strong>g behaviour. If content of bra<strong>in</strong> states is<br />

due to non-causal properties, this will not help <strong>the</strong><br />

reductionist, for <strong>the</strong> reductionist needs causal-functional<br />

def<strong>in</strong>itions. If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, content is due to causal<br />

role <strong>in</strong> controll<strong>in</strong>g behaviour, <strong>the</strong> reductionist still faces <strong>the</strong><br />

problem of def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tentional states <strong>in</strong> terms of<br />

behaviour. And as we just saw, because of <strong>the</strong> normativity<br />

condition, that problem seems hard to solve. So it seems<br />

that sentences <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> head will not be of much help to <strong>the</strong><br />

reductionist. This, of course, is not a problem for Fodor,<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce he is not a reductionist.<br />

Still ano<strong>the</strong>r reductionist <strong>the</strong>ory of mental content is<br />

teleosemantics, which purports to account for content <strong>in</strong><br />

terms of evolutionary selection history (see e.g. Millikan<br />

1984). But teleosemantics is a historical, not a causalfunctional<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory. This means that, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> teleosemantic<br />

view, content does not supervene on <strong>the</strong> totality of<br />

causally relevant facts about <strong>the</strong> present (see Dretske<br />

2006, 75). And this rules out <strong>the</strong> possibility of causalfunctional<br />

def<strong>in</strong>itions of <strong>in</strong>tentional states. So<br />

teleosemantics is not an option for a Kim-style reductionist.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, teleosemantics does not aim at reduction<br />

through functional def<strong>in</strong>ition, but reduction through identity.<br />

4. Conclusion<br />

I hope my discussion this far to have shown that <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

some a priori, philosophical grounds to doubt <strong>the</strong> possibility<br />

of m<strong>in</strong>d-body reduction through functional def<strong>in</strong>ition. I<br />

believe, though limitations of space prevent me from<br />

elaborat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t, that similar considerations apply<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong>ory reduction – <strong>the</strong> view that a correct <strong>the</strong>ory of<br />

<strong>the</strong> mental could <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple be derived from an allencompass<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory of <strong>the</strong> physical – s<strong>in</strong>ce I see no o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

139

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!