02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Determ<strong>in</strong>ation of Form by Syntactic Employment:<br />

a Model <strong>and</strong> a Difficulty<br />

Col<strong>in</strong> Johnston, London, Engl<strong>and</strong>, UK<br />

1.<br />

An entity’s logical character, for Russell <strong>and</strong> Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>,<br />

is a matter of <strong>the</strong> ways <strong>in</strong> which it may comb<strong>in</strong>e with o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

entities to form atomic facts. Where Russell gives a <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

of <strong>the</strong> logical constitution of atomic facts, however, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong><br />

asserts that <strong>the</strong> ways <strong>in</strong> which entities comb<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong><br />

facts can be known only a posteriori through <strong>the</strong> process<br />

of analysis. 1 Russell was thus mistaken <strong>in</strong> Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

eyes <strong>in</strong> lay<strong>in</strong>g out as he did his logical variety of particulars<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> various k<strong>in</strong>ds of universal. Press<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Tractarian<br />

position, Ramsey claims that we know “noth<strong>in</strong>g whatever<br />

about <strong>the</strong> forms of atomic propositions”. We do not know,<br />

for example, “that <strong>the</strong>re are not atomic facts consist<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

two terms of <strong>the</strong> same type” (Ramsey 1990 p29).<br />

I shall suggest that this Tractarian agnosticism is <strong>in</strong><br />

tension with <strong>the</strong> Tractarian doctr<strong>in</strong>e that <strong>the</strong> logicosyntactic<br />

use of a sign determ<strong>in</strong>es a logical form. Imag<strong>in</strong>e<br />

a ‘world’ <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>re are only two forms (that is, logical<br />

types) of object <strong>and</strong> only one mode of comb<strong>in</strong>ation, a<br />

mode <strong>in</strong> which a s<strong>in</strong>gle object of each form is comb<strong>in</strong>ed.<br />

The symmetry of this world is such that <strong>the</strong> two object<br />

forms are <strong>in</strong>ternally <strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable. The <strong>in</strong>ternal<br />

character of each form is exhausted by its be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> form<br />

of an object whose only possibility for comb<strong>in</strong>ation is <strong>in</strong> a<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> mode with an object of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r form, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>ternal character of <strong>the</strong> mode of comb<strong>in</strong>ation is exhausted<br />

by its be<strong>in</strong>g a mode of comb<strong>in</strong>ation of one object of each<br />

form. Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s agnosticism regard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> forms of<br />

reality means that he cannot say <strong>in</strong> advance that reality<br />

does not, like our imag<strong>in</strong>ed ‘world’, <strong>in</strong>clude dist<strong>in</strong>ct but<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternally <strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable forms. A logico-syntactic use,<br />

however, is to determ<strong>in</strong>e a logical form by virtue of<br />

determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal nature of that form only. If reality<br />

turns out to <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>in</strong>ternally <strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable forms it<br />

follows that <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ation as envisaged of logical form<br />

by logico-syntactic use will not everywhere be possible.<br />

To br<strong>in</strong>g this concern <strong>in</strong>to focus I want to develop a<br />

simple, semi-formal account of syntactic use, of form, <strong>and</strong><br />

of <strong>the</strong> place of syntactic use <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ation of form.<br />

The account will be appropriately general to accommodate<br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s ignorance of <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> forms of<br />

reality. I do not claim that <strong>the</strong> semi-formal work is at every<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t implicit <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Tractatus. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> work is <strong>in</strong>tended<br />

as an elucidatory model of certa<strong>in</strong> Tractarian ideas.<br />

2.<br />

The notion to be developed is of an atomic syntactic system.<br />

An atomic syntactic system S has:<br />

156<br />

a vocabulary V of signs, <strong>and</strong><br />

a set T = {Mj: j∈J} of sign types<br />

1 See Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> 1961 5.55 – 5.5571. See also Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> 1993<br />

pp. 29-30 <strong>and</strong> Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> 1979 p. 42.)<br />

where each Mj⊆V <strong>and</strong> J is an <strong>in</strong>dex<strong>in</strong>g set. Signs here are<br />

typographically identified marks. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> system S<br />

has:<br />

a set C of manners of sign comb<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

A manner of sign comb<strong>in</strong>ation c∈C will be a manner of<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation of a determ<strong>in</strong>ate, f<strong>in</strong>ite number of ordered<br />

signs. The comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> mode c of <strong>the</strong> signs s1, s2, …, sn<br />

so ordered is denoted by c(s1, s2, …, sn). F<strong>in</strong>ally for S <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is, for each manner of comb<strong>in</strong>ation c∈C, a rule of <strong>the</strong> form:<br />

x1∈Mf(c,1), x2∈Mf(c,2), …, xn∈Mf(c,n) ⇔ c(x1, x2, …, xn)∈F<br />

where f is some (appropriately partial) function from C×ℕ to<br />

J. Set F is <strong>the</strong> set of formulae of S; it conta<strong>in</strong>s no members<br />

besides those provided by <strong>the</strong> system’s rules of comb<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

Note that <strong>the</strong> rules for membership of F have <strong>the</strong> form<br />

of equivalences. What is not allowed <strong>in</strong> a syntactic system<br />

is, say, c(s,t)∈F <strong>and</strong> c(u,v)∈F, but c(s,v)∉F. Each position<br />

<strong>in</strong> each manner of comb<strong>in</strong>ation determ<strong>in</strong>es a set of signs<br />

which figure <strong>in</strong> that position <strong>in</strong> a formula, <strong>and</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r or<br />

not a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> a mode of C of signs from V is a formula<br />

of <strong>the</strong> system depends on <strong>the</strong> signs’ positions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir membership of such sets only.<br />

Next we want to reach an idea of <strong>the</strong> structure of a<br />

syntactic system, abstract<strong>in</strong>g away from <strong>the</strong> signs <strong>and</strong><br />

manners of comb<strong>in</strong>ation deployed <strong>in</strong> any particular system<br />

<strong>in</strong>stantiat<strong>in</strong>g that structure. The thought here is that what is<br />

of structural <strong>in</strong>terest is simply <strong>the</strong> number of positions<br />

belong<strong>in</strong>g to each sign type <strong>in</strong> each manner of<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation. Thus let’s say:<br />

X∈T occurs n (≥0) times <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation c if, <strong>and</strong><br />

only if, X=Mj <strong>and</strong> exactly n of f(c,i) are equal to j<br />

And with this we make <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ition:<br />

Two atomic syntactic systems S1 <strong>and</strong> S2 with manners<br />

of comb<strong>in</strong>ation C1 <strong>and</strong> C2 <strong>and</strong> sets of syntactic<br />

mark-types T1 <strong>and</strong> T2, are isomorphic if, <strong>and</strong><br />

only if, <strong>the</strong>re exists a bijection α:C1→C2 <strong>and</strong> a bijection<br />

β:T1→T2 such that, for all c∈C1 <strong>and</strong> X∈T1,<br />

(X occurs n times <strong>in</strong> c) ⇔ (β(X) occurs n times <strong>in</strong><br />

α(c)).<br />

Such a bijection (α,β):C1×T1→C2×T2 is an isomorphism<br />

from S1 to S2.<br />

The notion of an atomic syntactic system <strong>and</strong> its<br />

structure is now given. Let’s take a look at what its <strong>in</strong>terest<br />

might be.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!