02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Rule-Follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Irreducibility of Intentional States<br />

Antti Heik<strong>in</strong>heimo, Jyväskylä, F<strong>in</strong>l<strong>and</strong><br />

1. <strong>Reduction</strong> through Functional Def<strong>in</strong>ition<br />

It is not always clear what exactly is meant when it is said<br />

that someth<strong>in</strong>g mental is reducible to someth<strong>in</strong>g physical.<br />

Thus, when debat<strong>in</strong>g about reductionism, it is important to<br />

keep <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d just which k<strong>in</strong>d of reduction one is talk<strong>in</strong>g<br />

about. One clearly def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> plausible notion of reduction<br />

comes from Jaegwon Kim. Reducibility is often taken<br />

to be a relation between two “levels”, such as <strong>the</strong> mental<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> physical level. Kim argues, plausibly <strong>in</strong> my op<strong>in</strong>ion,<br />

that so called bridge-laws that connect <strong>the</strong> two levels with<br />

empirical regularities, do not amount to reduction (Kim<br />

2005, 103-5). This is because both <strong>the</strong> higher- <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

lower-level phenomena need to be mentioned <strong>in</strong> a statement<br />

of a regular connection between phenomena at two<br />

different levels, whereas reduction requires an account of<br />

<strong>the</strong> higher-level phenomenon solely <strong>in</strong> terms of <strong>the</strong> lower<br />

level. I take this much to be common ground between most<br />

reductionists <strong>and</strong> non-reductionists – that it is not enough<br />

for <strong>the</strong> reductionist to establish empirical connections between<br />

<strong>the</strong> mental <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> physical. He/She needs someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

stronger. In Kim’s view this stronger requirement is:<br />

138<br />

Conceptual connections, e.g., def<strong>in</strong>itions, provid<strong>in</strong>g<br />

conceptual/semantic relations between <strong>the</strong> phenomena<br />

at <strong>the</strong> two levels. (Kim 2005, 108)<br />

These conceptual connections serve as <strong>the</strong> first step of a<br />

reductive explanation, <strong>in</strong> terms of <strong>the</strong> “base” level, of <strong>the</strong><br />

phenomenon to be reduced. The reductive explanation<br />

consists of three steps:<br />

Step 1 (functionalization of <strong>the</strong> target property)<br />

Property M to be reduced is given a functional def<strong>in</strong>ition<br />

of <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g form: Hav<strong>in</strong>g M =def. hav<strong>in</strong>g<br />

some property or o<strong>the</strong>r P (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> reduction base doma<strong>in</strong>)<br />

such that P performs causal task C.<br />

Step 2 (Identification of <strong>the</strong> realizers of M) F<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong><br />

properties (or mechanisms) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> reduction base<br />

that perform <strong>the</strong> causal task C.<br />

Step 3 (Develop<strong>in</strong>g an explanatory <strong>the</strong>ory) Construct<br />

a <strong>the</strong>ory that expla<strong>in</strong>s how <strong>the</strong> realizers of M<br />

perform task C. (Kim 2005, 101-2)<br />

On this model, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> reduction of a higher-level property,<br />

such as be<strong>in</strong>g a gene, consists of (1) a functional<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ition, such as “be<strong>in</strong>g a gene = def. be<strong>in</strong>g a mechanism<br />

that encodes <strong>and</strong> transmits genetic <strong>in</strong>formation”; (2) f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> realizers for <strong>the</strong> causal-functional role – <strong>in</strong> this case,<br />

DNA molecules; <strong>and</strong> (3) a <strong>the</strong>ory – <strong>in</strong> our case molecular<br />

biology – that expla<strong>in</strong>s how <strong>the</strong> realizers – <strong>the</strong> DNA molecules<br />

– fulfil this role (Kim 2005, 101). In <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d-body<br />

case, <strong>the</strong> higher-level properties <strong>in</strong> question are such as<br />

“be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a mental state S”.<br />

Although Kim’s notion of reduction through<br />

functional def<strong>in</strong>ition is not, by any means, <strong>the</strong> only<br />

<strong>in</strong>telligible concept of reduction, I will make it <strong>the</strong> target of<br />

my follow<strong>in</strong>g discussion on reductionism. In <strong>the</strong> end of this<br />

paper I will <strong>in</strong>clude a very brief comment on <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

reduction <strong>and</strong> reduction through m<strong>in</strong>d-body identity. There<br />

are a few th<strong>in</strong>gs to notice about this reduction schema.<br />

First, <strong>the</strong> functional def<strong>in</strong>ition should, of course, be<br />

adequate to <strong>the</strong> established mean<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> higher-level<br />

concept. It is sometimes said that, because of some<br />

<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>iteness of everyday-language concepts, <strong>the</strong>y can<br />

not, strictly speak<strong>in</strong>g, be def<strong>in</strong>ed. S<strong>in</strong>ce this is obviously<br />

not <strong>the</strong> real issue between reductionists <strong>and</strong> nonreductionists,<br />

‘def<strong>in</strong>ition’ here should be understood <strong>in</strong> a<br />

relaxed sense, mean<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g like “rough<br />

characterization”. Second, it is <strong>the</strong> atta<strong>in</strong>ability of <strong>the</strong><br />

functional def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>in</strong> step 1 that is essential to <strong>the</strong><br />

philosophical issue of reductionism vs. non-reductionism. If<br />

step 1 can be completed, i.e. adequate def<strong>in</strong>itions of <strong>the</strong><br />

higher-level properties can be given through causal roles,<br />

but <strong>the</strong> reduction never<strong>the</strong>less fails <strong>in</strong> steps 2 <strong>and</strong> 3, <strong>the</strong><br />

result<strong>in</strong>g position will not be non-reductionism (at least not<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> usual sense of that word), but elim<strong>in</strong>ativism (if <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are no realizers for <strong>the</strong> roles specified) 1 . Third, <strong>the</strong><br />

philosophical debate over reductionism (or at least <strong>the</strong> one<br />

I have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d) concerns <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple or <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

atta<strong>in</strong>ability of <strong>the</strong> functional def<strong>in</strong>itions, not <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

atta<strong>in</strong>ability <strong>in</strong> practice.<br />

We are now <strong>in</strong> a position to see what would<br />

constitute a conclusive argument for ei<strong>the</strong>r side <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

reductionism debate. The m<strong>in</strong>d-body reductionist needs to<br />

show that<br />

MBR 2 It is <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple possible to def<strong>in</strong>e mental<br />

properties, adequately to <strong>the</strong> established mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>in</strong> question, with recourse to causalfunctional<br />

roles, not us<strong>in</strong>g mental property concepts<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>iens.<br />

The non-reductionist, respectively, needs to show that<br />

MBR is not true, i.e. that it is not possible, even <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple,<br />

to give such def<strong>in</strong>itions.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Kim, functional def<strong>in</strong>itions are not<br />

atta<strong>in</strong>able for concepts of phenomenal properties, but are<br />

atta<strong>in</strong>able for concepts of <strong>in</strong>tentional/cognitive properties,<br />

such as believ<strong>in</strong>g that p or desir<strong>in</strong>g that q (Kim 2005). I will<br />

argue that functional def<strong>in</strong>itions are not atta<strong>in</strong>able <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

case of <strong>in</strong>tentional properties ei<strong>the</strong>r, that is, that MBR does<br />

not hold for <strong>in</strong>tentional properties.<br />

2. The Normativity Argument<br />

My argument is based on <strong>the</strong> discussion on rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> Saul Kripke’s Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> on Rules <strong>and</strong> Private Language<br />

(Kripke 1982). Kripke’s question was, approximately,<br />

“what makes it <strong>the</strong> case that, <strong>in</strong> say<strong>in</strong>g ‘plus’ <strong>and</strong><br />

us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> + symbol, I mean addition <strong>and</strong> not some o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

function?” His answer was, roughly, that <strong>the</strong>re is noth<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

no fact, short of <strong>the</strong> whole practices of attribut<strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

<strong>and</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g addition <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> community of languageusers<br />

that makes <strong>the</strong> difference between my mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

one th<strong>in</strong>g or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. Kripke specially considers one sort<br />

of facts that might be thought to make <strong>the</strong> difference.<br />

Namely, facts about my dispositions to use <strong>the</strong> word ‘plus’<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> + symbol. Now <strong>the</strong>se dispositions are exactly <strong>the</strong><br />

k<strong>in</strong>d of causal-functional roles that appear <strong>in</strong> Kim-style<br />

reductive explanations. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, functionally def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

1 That is, if we have conclusive grounds for claim<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>re are no realizers<br />

for <strong>the</strong> causal roles. If we have just not yet managed to f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> right realizers,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n, of course, we do not have to give <strong>in</strong> to elim<strong>in</strong>ativism.<br />

2 For m<strong>in</strong>d-body reductionism.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!