02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

supposedly <strong>in</strong>ductive, for, as it is often said, “<strong>in</strong>duction is<br />

<strong>the</strong> method of science”. So he <strong>in</strong>fers <strong>the</strong> future of science<br />

from its past: S<strong>in</strong>ce science has progressed <strong>and</strong> has managed<br />

to illum<strong>in</strong>ate some issues concern<strong>in</strong>g human consciousness,<br />

it will evolve more <strong>and</strong> resolve all relevant<br />

questions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> future. Yet, his argument goes beyond<br />

<strong>in</strong>duction; it ra<strong>the</strong>r appeals to Churchl<strong>and</strong>’ s <strong>in</strong>tuitions<br />

about <strong>the</strong> future of science <strong>and</strong> of ord<strong>in</strong>ary language. For<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no evidence nowadays that beliefs <strong>and</strong> desires will<br />

be elim<strong>in</strong>ated from our folk vocabulary. We have no clue<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r science (perhaps some new branch of science)<br />

will embrace <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>to our common natural history or even<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r this whole natural history will prove <strong>in</strong>accurate <strong>and</strong><br />

change. From our current viewpo<strong>in</strong>t all <strong>the</strong>se hypo<strong>the</strong>ses<br />

are mere speculation.<br />

Meanwhile, Churchl<strong>and</strong> identifies explanation with<br />

<strong>the</strong> reduction of any phenomenon <strong>in</strong>to physical<br />

phenomenon. Yet, he has no full-fledged, specific<br />

paradigms of such a reduction to offer. Fail<strong>in</strong>g an<br />

alternative coherent description of mental phenomena, his<br />

<strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ontology of ord<strong>in</strong>ary language<br />

seems impracticable. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> identification of<br />

scientific explanation <strong>and</strong> physical reduction restricts <strong>the</strong><br />

concept of science, without even def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g it conceivably.<br />

The hard naturalist, though, can answer this l<strong>in</strong>e of<br />

criticism: be<strong>in</strong>g a philosopher (<strong>and</strong> thus a proto-scientist)<br />

<strong>the</strong>y don’t need to provide a full-fledged <strong>the</strong>ory to take folk<br />

psychology’s place. (Churchl<strong>and</strong>, 1986, p.6). They only<br />

need to give an outl<strong>in</strong>e of what this <strong>the</strong>ory should be like;<br />

<strong>and</strong>, accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>m, this proto-<strong>the</strong>ory is already be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

built. (Churchl<strong>and</strong>, 1991, p.67)<br />

Yet Churchl<strong>and</strong> views suffer an imm<strong>in</strong>ent tension:<br />

he takes for granted that many concepts, that are basic for<br />

communication <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, are pseudo-concepts<br />

with no literal mean<strong>in</strong>g. Meanwhile, <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> concepts,<br />

which we are brought up with. From day one, we learn to<br />

engage those concepts <strong>and</strong> use <strong>the</strong>m to underst<strong>and</strong> all<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is around us, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g science. Ord<strong>in</strong>ary language is<br />

full of mental vocabulary <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> way we approach all<br />

human experience is full of folk psychology presumptions<br />

<strong>and</strong> explanations. Official education teaches us to th<strong>in</strong>k<br />

us<strong>in</strong>g such concepts descriptions <strong>and</strong> explanations. The<br />

phenomena we approach are described by <strong>the</strong>m; all our<br />

start<strong>in</strong>g hypo<strong>the</strong>ses <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>the</strong>m. These are <strong>the</strong> concepts<br />

Churchl<strong>and</strong> himself uses: when he says that folk<br />

psychology is a pseudo-<strong>the</strong>ory he expresses a belief of<br />

his, <strong>the</strong>re is no o<strong>the</strong>r way to say it.<br />

Of course, one would answer that this only goes for<br />

now; when folk psychology gets elim<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>the</strong>re will be<br />

some o<strong>the</strong>r, better way to say it. (Churchl<strong>and</strong>, 1981, p.87)<br />

But for <strong>the</strong> time be<strong>in</strong>g those are <strong>the</strong> only concepts we<br />

have; it is through <strong>the</strong>m that today’s scientists are tra<strong>in</strong>ed.<br />

If we accuse <strong>the</strong>m of be<strong>in</strong>g void, we can no longer sensibly<br />

tra<strong>in</strong> today’s scientists. Nei<strong>the</strong>r can we sensibly articulate<br />

today’s hypo<strong>the</strong>ses or <strong>the</strong>ories.<br />

Elim<strong>in</strong>ative naturalists such as Churchl<strong>and</strong> write <strong>and</strong><br />

teach <strong>in</strong> a language <strong>the</strong>y consider mean<strong>in</strong>gless. But you<br />

cannot teach us<strong>in</strong>g a language <strong>and</strong> simultaneously<br />

suggest that most concepts <strong>and</strong> dispositions embedded <strong>in</strong><br />

this language are senseless. This only makes what you<br />

say senseless as well.<br />

4. Conclusion<br />

Naturalism sees science <strong>and</strong> scientific method as a valid<br />

way people have <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir attempt to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. But<br />

how do people get engaged <strong>in</strong>to scientific method(s)?<br />

118<br />

Hard Naturalism <strong>and</strong> its Puzzles — Renia Gasparatou<br />

Does naturalism manage a <strong>the</strong>oretical explanation of how<br />

scientific education <strong>and</strong> evolution work?<br />

Hard naturalism identifies scientific explanation with<br />

an ideal physicalistic reduction. Yet, hard naturalists such<br />

as Churchl<strong>and</strong> offer no strict criteria about what physical<br />

means: is meteorology a physical science? Is cognitive<br />

psychology a purely physical science today? Science<br />

seems restricted <strong>in</strong>to very few branches <strong>and</strong>, what’s more,<br />

one cannot even know <strong>the</strong> criterion by which a discipl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

qualifies as scientific. Churchl<strong>and</strong> offers only some <strong>in</strong>tuitive<br />

remarks about how <strong>the</strong> scientific worldview will be like by<br />

propos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> elim<strong>in</strong>ation of all terms that today’s science<br />

has trouble account<strong>in</strong>g for.<br />

Moreover, by <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g that all non-reducible terms<br />

should be elim<strong>in</strong>ated form our explanatory story, <strong>the</strong> hard<br />

naturalist restricts <strong>the</strong> phenomena <strong>in</strong> need of explanation<br />

<strong>in</strong>to very few. Many questions posed by today’s people<br />

(psychological or ethical worries <strong>and</strong> troubles) are<br />

considered pseudo-questions, raised by <strong>the</strong> pseudo-<strong>the</strong>ory<br />

of folk psychology, which our language supports.<br />

Most importantly, Churchl<strong>and</strong>’ s hard naturalism,<br />

despite <strong>the</strong> scientism it implies, does not manage to<br />

illum<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong> very fact of scientific education <strong>and</strong><br />

evolution. It makes it <strong>in</strong>comprehensible that people who<br />

teach <strong>and</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong>to pseudo-terms produce new good<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories <strong>and</strong> educate new scientists that help science<br />

evolve. If our language is full of pseudo-concepts <strong>and</strong> false<br />

ontology, it is a mystery how scientific education was made<br />

to work <strong>and</strong> still cont<strong>in</strong>ues to do. Consequently, it is a<br />

mystery how science progressed <strong>and</strong> still cont<strong>in</strong>ues to do<br />

so. The conceptual rules used <strong>in</strong> everyday life are <strong>the</strong><br />

same rules <strong>the</strong> scientist uses, even with<strong>in</strong> his technical<br />

vocabulary. And despite this very fact, new scientists learn<br />

good science, make valid hypo<strong>the</strong>ses <strong>and</strong> produce<br />

compell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ories. Even <strong>the</strong> most revolutionary among<br />

<strong>the</strong>m rely, at least at first, on common world picture. Or,<br />

even when <strong>the</strong>y question it, <strong>the</strong>y are articulated <strong>in</strong><br />

language.<br />

It seems that <strong>the</strong> primacy ascribed to science comes<br />

with a high price: it makes science “st<strong>and</strong> alone, without<br />

visible prospect of reduction to that larger corpus”, to<br />

paraphrase Churchl<strong>and</strong>. (1981, p.75) Accord<strong>in</strong>g to him,<br />

scientific practice is not part of human practices but st<strong>and</strong>s<br />

way above <strong>the</strong>m. It is <strong>the</strong> primary explanatory method <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> one that will eventually elim<strong>in</strong>ate all o<strong>the</strong>r branches. It<br />

will elim<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong> problems o<strong>the</strong>r disciples confront, even<br />

<strong>the</strong> vocabulary that gives rise to those questions. But if<br />

one puts science so much higher than any o<strong>the</strong>r human<br />

practice, <strong>the</strong>y cut its every connection with <strong>the</strong> community<br />

it comes from, <strong>the</strong> very community that practices it. Hard<br />

naturalist’s scientism has to face this paradox: <strong>the</strong> very<br />

primacy of science’s explanatory methods makes it harder<br />

to expla<strong>in</strong> how science is communicated <strong>and</strong> evolved.<br />

Literature<br />

Churchl<strong>and</strong>, P.M. 1981, “Elim<strong>in</strong>ative Materialism <strong>and</strong> Propositional<br />

Attitudes”, Journal of <strong>Philosophy</strong> 78, 67-90.<br />

Churchl<strong>and</strong>, P.M. 1986, “On <strong>the</strong> Cont<strong>in</strong>uity of Science <strong>and</strong> <strong>Philosophy</strong>”,<br />

M<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> Language 1, 5-14.<br />

Churchl<strong>and</strong>, P.M. 1989, “Folk Psychology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Explanation of<br />

Human Behavior”, Philosophical Perspectives 3, 225-241.<br />

Strawson, P.F. 1985, Skepticism <strong>and</strong> Naturalism: Some Varieties,<br />

London: Methuen & Co. Ltd.<br />

Stroud, B. 1996, “The Charm of Naturalism”, Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong><br />

Addresses of <strong>the</strong> American Philosophical Association, 70 (2), 43-55.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!