02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Qu<strong>in</strong>e on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Reduction</strong> of Mean<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

Lieven Decock, Amsterdam, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s semantic nihilism is well-known. From his earliest<br />

work onwards, he expelled mean<strong>in</strong>gs from his ontology.<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> important <strong>in</strong>novations <strong>in</strong> his doctoral <strong>the</strong>sis, The<br />

Logic of Sequences, which is a reworked version of<br />

Whitehead <strong>and</strong> Russell’s Pr<strong>in</strong>cipia Ma<strong>the</strong>matica, was<br />

extensionalism. Qu<strong>in</strong>e replaced <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensional<br />

propositional functions by extensional classes. Dur<strong>in</strong>g his<br />

trip to Europe <strong>in</strong> 1933, he discovered that this had become<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard practice <strong>in</strong> Europe, <strong>and</strong> has defended<br />

extensionalism ever s<strong>in</strong>ce, even <strong>in</strong> his latest writ<strong>in</strong>gs. The<br />

only universals one should accept are classes. He<br />

regarded classes or sets as bona fide objects, because<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is a clear criterion of identity, viz. classes can be<br />

identified through <strong>the</strong>ir members. For <strong>in</strong>tensions no such<br />

criterion is available, so <strong>the</strong>y cannot be hypostasised<br />

(1960:244). For some years, Qu<strong>in</strong>e also tried to get rid of<br />

classes (Qu<strong>in</strong>e 1936; Goodman & Qu<strong>in</strong>e 1947), but he<br />

came to recognize <strong>the</strong> necessity of posit<strong>in</strong>g sets, thus<br />

giv<strong>in</strong>g up strict nom<strong>in</strong>alism.<br />

Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s extensionalism has determ<strong>in</strong>ed his views on<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> semantics. Attributes or mean<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>tensional components of universals, are only acceptable<br />

if <strong>the</strong>y can be given a clear criterion of identity. In practice,<br />

this meant that mean<strong>in</strong>gs are only acceptable <strong>in</strong>sofar <strong>the</strong>y<br />

can be reduced to clearly identifiable objects, i.e. classes<br />

of classes, … , of physical objects. In Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s work, one<br />

can f<strong>in</strong>d two concrete proposals for such a reduction. In<br />

<strong>the</strong> first proposal empirical mean<strong>in</strong>gs are characterised as<br />

stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>gs, i.e. classes of physical stimuli, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

second <strong>the</strong>y are classes of l<strong>in</strong>guistic expressions. Qu<strong>in</strong>e<br />

judges both proposals unsuccessful.<br />

Qu<strong>in</strong>e def<strong>in</strong>es a stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong> ordered<br />

pair of <strong>the</strong> affirmative stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> negative<br />

stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>g (1960:31-35). The affirmative stimulus<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>the</strong> class of all stimulations to which a given<br />

speaker at a date would assent; <strong>the</strong> negative stimulus<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> class of stimulation to which she would<br />

dissent. The proposal can be sharpened by us<strong>in</strong>g reaction<br />

time to measure doubt, or by <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g a modulus, i.e. a<br />

maximum time duration for stimulations. So far, stimulus<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g is reduced to an ordered pair of classes of<br />

stimulations. An ordered pair can be reduced by means of<br />

Kuratowski’s or Wiener’s reduction method to sets (1960<br />

§53). Hence, a stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>g is clearly identifiable if<br />

stimulations can be reduced to simpler entities. The<br />

stimulations can be ocular irradiation patterns toge<strong>the</strong>r with<br />

“<strong>the</strong> various barrages of o<strong>the</strong>r senses, separately <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> all<br />

synchronous comb<strong>in</strong>ations” (1960:33). Ocular irradiation<br />

patterns are types of evolv<strong>in</strong>g chromatic irradiation<br />

patterns of all durations up to some modulus. An<br />

alternative is def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g an external momentary stimulation<br />

as “<strong>the</strong> set of [a person’s] triggered receptors.” (1981:50)<br />

Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s notion of stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>g is unproblematic from<br />

a reductionist po<strong>in</strong>t of view. Empirical mean<strong>in</strong>gs are<br />

reduced by means of reduction strategies that are<br />

acceptable for Qu<strong>in</strong>e to entities that Qu<strong>in</strong>e f<strong>in</strong>ds<br />

unproblematic, namely physical objects <strong>and</strong> classes.<br />

The reduction strategy is clearly <strong>in</strong>spired by<br />

Carnap’s reduction programme <strong>in</strong> Der logische Aufbau der<br />

Welt. Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s worries concern<strong>in</strong>g stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>g accord<br />

with his objections to Carnap’s early reduction programme<br />

<strong>and</strong> his later verification <strong>the</strong>ory of mean<strong>in</strong>g (Carnap 1936).<br />

64<br />

Qu<strong>in</strong>e believes that stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>g is restricted to<br />

observation sentences, whereas most sentences are not<br />

immediately l<strong>in</strong>ked to sensory stimulations. Only sentences<br />

at <strong>the</strong> boundary of <strong>the</strong> web of belief have stimulus<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g, but this is only a small fraction of all sentences.<br />

Hence, stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>g is not a viable basis for<br />

semantics, because <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of most sentences<br />

cannot be expla<strong>in</strong>ed as stimulus mean<strong>in</strong>g. In brief, Qu<strong>in</strong>e<br />

has given an impeccable reduction strategy, <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong><br />

same time po<strong>in</strong>ted out its severe limitations.<br />

In Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s second reduction strategy, “we could<br />

def<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of an expression as <strong>the</strong> class of all<br />

expressions like it <strong>in</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g.” (1992:52; see also<br />

1960:201; 1979:140; 1981:46). The reduction of<br />

expressions is unproblematic, ei<strong>the</strong>r to classes (via Gödel<br />

number<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> reduction of numbers to sets) or to<br />

classes of physical objects (<strong>in</strong>scriptions). More noteworthy,<br />

<strong>the</strong> class of mean<strong>in</strong>gful expressions can be precisely<br />

del<strong>in</strong>eated <strong>in</strong> grammar (see Decock 2002:86). For <strong>the</strong><br />

reduction strategy to work, <strong>the</strong> only fur<strong>the</strong>r requirement is<br />

that a precise characterisation of <strong>the</strong> dyadic predicate “x is<br />

alike <strong>in</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g with y” or “x is synonymous with y” is<br />

elaborated. In his early work, Qu<strong>in</strong>e is extremely sceptical<br />

about this notion of synonymy, especially for st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

sentences (1960:201). Of course, one can use stimulus<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g to def<strong>in</strong>e synonymy, <strong>and</strong> even with <strong>the</strong> help of<br />

first order logic extend this notion to ‘cognitive synonymy’<br />

(1979), but this will not help for st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g sentences. The<br />

only alternative is to characterise synonymy by means of<br />

<strong>the</strong> notion of analyticity: “Once we have analyticity,<br />

cognitive equivalence is forthcom<strong>in</strong>g; for two sentences<br />

are cognitive equivalent if <strong>and</strong> only if <strong>the</strong>ir truth-functional<br />

biconditional is analytic.” (1992:54f) In view of Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s<br />

well-known demise of <strong>the</strong> analytic-syn<strong>the</strong>tic dist<strong>in</strong>ction, this<br />

looks like a dead end.<br />

However, <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>terview on <strong>the</strong> occasion of <strong>the</strong> Rolf<br />

Schock prize <strong>in</strong> November 1993, Qu<strong>in</strong>e said:<br />

Yes so, on this score I th<strong>in</strong>k of <strong>the</strong> truths of logic as<br />

analytic <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> traditional sense of <strong>the</strong> word, that is<br />

to say true by virtue of <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> words.<br />

Or as I would prefer to put it: <strong>the</strong>y are learned or can<br />

be learned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> process of learn<strong>in</strong>g to use <strong>the</strong><br />

words <strong>the</strong>mselves, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>volve noth<strong>in</strong>g more. They<br />

are analytic <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same sense <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

example such as “No bachelor is married”, is<br />

analytic: someth<strong>in</strong>g that’s learned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> process of<br />

learn<strong>in</strong>g to use <strong>the</strong> word “bachelor” itself.<br />

(Bergström & Føllesdal 1994, 199f)<br />

This passage <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r more covert passages (1974:79;<br />

1992:55) look like a recantation of one of Qu<strong>in</strong>e’s most<br />

famous claims. Qu<strong>in</strong>e admits that <strong>the</strong>orems of first order<br />

logic can be analytic, <strong>and</strong> that sentences such as “No<br />

bachelor is married” can be analytic. It is arguable that<br />

Qu<strong>in</strong>e has regarded first order logic as analytic s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong><br />

end of <strong>the</strong> 1940s, or even propositional logic as analytic<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce ‘Truth by convention’ (1936). Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> claim<br />

that “No bachelor is married” can be analytic, is a radical<br />

departure from earlier claims. Qu<strong>in</strong>e here offers a clear<br />

behaviouristic characterisation of analyticity. This fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

implies that synonymy <strong>and</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g become unproblematic,<br />

at least for expressions that are analytically equiva-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!