02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

On <strong>the</strong> Characterization of Objects by <strong>the</strong> Language of Science — Paul We<strong>in</strong>gartner<br />

world or <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r (physically) possible world. Therefore it<br />

is not determ<strong>in</strong>ed by any law whe<strong>the</strong>r some <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>itial<br />

state of our world can be found <strong>in</strong> any of <strong>the</strong> (physically)<br />

possible o<strong>the</strong>r worlds. What has been said is particularly<br />

true of <strong>the</strong> dynamical laws of Classical Mechanics.<br />

Consequently, although a dynamical law connects two<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual states of this (our) world <strong>and</strong> although it will connect<br />

two <strong>in</strong>dividual states <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r world, it does not<br />

connect two <strong>in</strong>dividual states of two different worlds.<br />

From this it follows immediately that trans-worldidentity<br />

of <strong>in</strong>dividual states is not guaranteed <strong>in</strong> Classical<br />

Mechanics.<br />

The same holds for <strong>the</strong> objects of reference of<br />

Classical Mechanics: for any such object (⎫x)φx satisfy<strong>in</strong>g<br />

uniqueness, its identity cannot be guaranteed <strong>in</strong> any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

possible world, <strong>in</strong>dependently of how <strong>the</strong> accessibility<br />

relation is def<strong>in</strong>ed. Although such an object is reidentifiable<br />

<strong>in</strong> one world, it is not from one world to ano<strong>the</strong>r one. 12<br />

From this it follows that an application of Kripke's<br />

semantics to Classical Mechanics will lead only to a<br />

redundant extension; s<strong>in</strong>ce its <strong>in</strong>terpretation of "possible"<br />

<strong>and</strong> "necessary" reduces to factual (true or false) <strong>in</strong> this<br />

(our) world.<br />

3. Are <strong>the</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples about <strong>the</strong> Objects of<br />

Reference (Listed <strong>in</strong> Ch. 2) valid when<br />

applied to <strong>the</strong> Microlevel (Quantum<br />

Physics)?<br />

3.1 Value-Completeness<br />

Applied to stable elementary particles like electrons, protons<br />

<strong>and</strong> neutrons (or to stable composed systems) <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is no general value-completeness or value-def<strong>in</strong>iteness;<br />

i.e. <strong>the</strong> object of reference is, <strong>in</strong> general, not a bearer of<br />

value-def<strong>in</strong>ite (value-complete) properties (cf. 2.4 above).<br />

At time t <strong>the</strong> object, as known through measurement results,<br />

can be <strong>the</strong> bearer only of a selected or limited number<br />

of properties, i.e. those which are mutually commensurable.<br />

The conceptual construction of <strong>the</strong> object as it is<br />

known by measurement results (Russell's logical<br />

construction) is necessarily <strong>in</strong>complete. Therefore <strong>the</strong><br />

description (⎫x)φx of such an object, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is not value<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite (cf. 2.4), will not satisfy uniqueness. As a<br />

consequence of that, <strong>the</strong> conceptual construction (or <strong>the</strong><br />

logical construction) which is <strong>in</strong>complete cannot – <strong>in</strong><br />

general – be identified with <strong>the</strong> reference. Thus if we<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> conceptual construction as <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g, it<br />

should not be identified with <strong>the</strong> reference (<strong>in</strong><br />

contradist<strong>in</strong>ction to Russell).<br />

3.2 Permutation Invariance<br />

The Schröd<strong>in</strong>ger equation holds for k<strong>in</strong>ds of objects, not<br />

for s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>dividual objects. In general: <strong>the</strong> laws of Quantum<br />

Mechanics (QM) are permutationally <strong>in</strong>variant, i.e.<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong>variant with respect to an exchange of particles<br />

of <strong>the</strong> same k<strong>in</strong>d. This means that different <strong>in</strong>dividual (numerically<br />

different) particles of <strong>the</strong> same k<strong>in</strong>d are treated<br />

identically by <strong>the</strong> laws. The laws do not dist<strong>in</strong>guish between<br />

two electrons, two protons… etc.; <strong>the</strong>y rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

12 For a detailed justification cf. Mittelstaedt (1986, SRM), p. 241ff.<br />

same laws when we exchange two electrons, two protons,<br />

two neutrons or also two photons. 13<br />

From this it follows that one of <strong>the</strong> conditions for<br />

(⎫x)φx – <strong>the</strong> condition that at most one x satisfies φx – is<br />

violated s<strong>in</strong>ce more than one object (a whole class of<br />

objects of he same k<strong>in</strong>d) satisfies <strong>the</strong> law. Thus<br />

uniqueness of <strong>the</strong> QM-object is not satisfied.<br />

3.3 Uniqueness<br />

A QM-object can also not be uniquely described as an<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual object by accidental properties. Recall (2.6<br />

above) that an object of Classical Mechanics can be so<br />

described, namely by <strong>the</strong> three magnitudes of position (p),<br />

momentum (q) <strong>and</strong> time (t). The reason that this is not<br />

possible for <strong>the</strong> QM-object is because <strong>the</strong> totality of accidental<br />

properties which were needed for <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualisation<br />

(uniqueness) is not available at <strong>the</strong> same time. That is<br />

<strong>the</strong> description by accidental properties is never complete<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus we cannot get uniqueness for <strong>the</strong> respective objects<br />

if <strong>the</strong>y are understood to be permanent <strong>in</strong> some (reasonable)<br />

way (cf. 3.4 below).<br />

3.4 Reidentification<br />

The QM-object is not identifiable through time, <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

temporal identity. In fact <strong>the</strong>re are <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g two possibilities:<br />

(a) There is a position measurement at t1, that is<br />

we can have uniqueness of <strong>the</strong> object (or state<br />

of <strong>the</strong> system) – impenetrability presupposed –<br />

only at <strong>the</strong> time po<strong>in</strong>t t1; <strong>in</strong> this case <strong>the</strong> object<br />

(or state) dissolves later at t2 such that we do<br />

not have uniqueness anymore, i.e. no permanent<br />

object.<br />

(b) The two states ψ(t1) <strong>and</strong> ψ(t2) are connected<br />

by a law of QM through time (t1, t2). But <strong>in</strong> this<br />

case only ψ(t1) is unique w.r.t. one object or<br />

state (or system); s<strong>in</strong>ce ψ(t2) can <strong>the</strong>n be satisfied<br />

by more than one object (state or system),<br />

it <strong>the</strong>refore does not guarantee to designate<br />

<strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al unique object (state, system).<br />

Although <strong>the</strong>re is permanence given by <strong>the</strong><br />

connection of <strong>the</strong> law, <strong>the</strong>re is no guarantee<br />

that what is connected is <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al object<br />

(system) at a later time. 14<br />

3.5 Trans-World-Identity<br />

For quantum mechanical objects or systems uniqueness<br />

(<strong>the</strong> condition for us<strong>in</strong>g (⎫x)φx) is not satisfied. The reason<br />

is this: <strong>the</strong> characterisation by <strong>the</strong>ir essential <strong>and</strong> permanent<br />

properties fails because with <strong>the</strong>m only classes of<br />

objects or systems (like electrons, protons, photons) can<br />

be determ<strong>in</strong>ed. But also a characterisation by accidental<br />

properties like position <strong>and</strong> momentum at a certa<strong>in</strong> time is<br />

impossible s<strong>in</strong>ce only a part of such properties are simultaneously<br />

available. Still ano<strong>the</strong>r possibility for a unique<br />

characterisation would be a description of a sufficiently<br />

complete historical development of <strong>the</strong> object (<strong>in</strong>stead of<br />

giv<strong>in</strong>g only <strong>the</strong> actual properties at a certa<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t of<br />

time). 15 However, it is an unsolved problem how such a<br />

13 For more on permutational symmetry cf. Mittelstaedt/We<strong>in</strong>gartner (2005,<br />

LNt), p. 74, 77, 82.<br />

14 For more details see Mittelstaedt (1986, SRM), p. 227ff.<br />

15 The idea to use <strong>the</strong> history of <strong>the</strong> human actions <strong>and</strong> decisions as a<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of <strong>in</strong>dividuation of human souls (after separation from human body –<br />

385

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!