02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Reduc<strong>in</strong>g Sets to Modalities<br />

Rafał Urbaniak, Ghent, Belgium<br />

The ultimate aim here is to provide a modal <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

of <strong>the</strong> language of set <strong>the</strong>ory. Let us start with <strong>the</strong> question<br />

of ontological commitment of plural quantification. First, I<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduce <strong>the</strong> language of Quantified Name Logic (QNL)<br />

<strong>and</strong> provide it with a set-<strong>the</strong>oretic semantics.<br />

The language of QNL is generated by <strong>the</strong> alphabet<br />

conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g brackets, name variables:<br />

a1, a2, a3,... (as an abbreviation, also a, b, c, d, ...<br />

possibly with numerical subscripts),<br />

<strong>the</strong> constant ε, <strong>the</strong> existential quantifier (∃a) (<strong>the</strong> universal<br />

quantifier (∀) has its usual def<strong>in</strong>ition), <strong>and</strong> two Boolean<br />

connectives: negation ¬, <strong>and</strong> conjunction &.<br />

The set of well-formed formulas of QNL is <strong>the</strong><br />

least set satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g conditions:<br />

(i) If a1 <strong>and</strong> a2 are name variables, ε(a1, a2) is a<br />

well-formed formula,<br />

(ii) If A1 <strong>and</strong> A2 are well-formed formulas <strong>and</strong> a is a<br />

name variable, also ¬(A1), &(A1, A2) <strong>and</strong><br />

(∃a)(A1) are well-formed formulas.<br />

I also freely move to <strong>in</strong>fix notation for <strong>the</strong> language.<br />

Quite an imparsimonious but a fairly st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

semantics for QNL is given as follows. 1 Take <strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong><br />

to be a set of objects <strong>and</strong> take <strong>the</strong> range of name variables<br />

to be <strong>the</strong> power set of <strong>the</strong> doma<strong>in</strong>. An S-model of QNL is a<br />

pair such that D is an arbitrary set <strong>and</strong> I is a total<br />

function which maps name variables <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> power set of<br />

D (i.e. to each name variable it assigns a subset of <strong>the</strong><br />

doma<strong>in</strong>). Nei<strong>the</strong>r D nor I(a) for any a has to be non-empty.<br />

Def<strong>in</strong>ition. Truth <strong>in</strong> an S-model is def<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

conditions:<br />

models ε(a, b) iff |I(a)| = 1 (i.e. I(a) is a s<strong>in</strong>gleton)<br />

<strong>and</strong> I(a) is a subset of I(b).<br />

Phrases for negation <strong>and</strong> conjunction are st<strong>and</strong>ard: a<br />

model models a negation iff it doesn’t model <strong>the</strong> negated<br />

formula, a model models a conjunction iff it<br />

models both conjuncts.<br />

models (∃a)A iff models A for some I a<br />

which differs from I at most at a.<br />

A sentence is S-valid iff it is true <strong>in</strong> any S-model. ∆<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard objections aga<strong>in</strong>st nom<strong>in</strong>alistic acceptability<br />

of <strong>the</strong> logic of plurals is that it needs a formal<br />

semantics, <strong>the</strong> set-<strong>the</strong>oretic semantics commits <strong>the</strong> pluralist<br />

to sets, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> substitutional <strong>in</strong>terpretation of plural<br />

quantification does not provide <strong>the</strong> language with <strong>the</strong> required<br />

expressive power (we “run out of tokens”, if <strong>the</strong>y're<br />

supposed to be f<strong>in</strong>ite str<strong>in</strong>gs over a f<strong>in</strong>ite alphabet). In<br />

order to provide an answer to that objection, I give a semisubstitutional<br />

semantics which avoids <strong>the</strong> objections usually<br />

raised aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> substitutional <strong>in</strong>terpretation of plural<br />

quantifiers.<br />

1 QNL is pretty much a variant of Boolos’s logic of plurals - <strong>the</strong> expressive<br />

power of both languages (modulo set-<strong>the</strong>oretic semantics) is <strong>the</strong> same.<br />

I develop a Kripke semantics for QNL. It is a<br />

modal <strong>in</strong>terpretation, where <strong>the</strong> plural quantifier ‘(∃a)’<br />

(suppose A does not conta<strong>in</strong> free variables o<strong>the</strong>r than a) is<br />

<strong>in</strong>tuitively read as ‘it is possible to <strong>in</strong>troduce a name a,<br />

which would make A substitutionally true’ (<strong>the</strong> semantics is<br />

different from that of Chihara). There are good reasons to<br />

claim that QNL with Kripke semantics has <strong>the</strong> same<br />

expressive power as QNL with set-<strong>the</strong>oretic semantics (as<br />

it turns out, for any set-<strong>the</strong>oretic model <strong>the</strong>re is a Kripke<br />

model which agrees with it on all QNL formulas <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r way round: for any Kripke model <strong>the</strong>re is a set<strong>the</strong>oretic<br />

model which agrees with it on all formulas).<br />

Def<strong>in</strong>ition. A nam<strong>in</strong>g structure is a tuple where I<br />

is a set (of bare <strong>in</strong>dividuals) <strong>and</strong> W is a set of possible<br />

worlds. A possible world is a tuple where I <strong>and</strong> N<br />

are disjo<strong>in</strong>t sets <strong>and</strong> d is a subset of <strong>the</strong> Cartesian product<br />

of N <strong>and</strong> I. A bare world is <strong>the</strong> possible world where N is<br />

<strong>the</strong> empty set (Φ). The follow<strong>in</strong>g conditions all have to be<br />

satisfied:<br />

B = belongs to W (i.e. <strong>the</strong> nam<strong>in</strong>g structure<br />

conta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> bare world).<br />

For any w <strong>in</strong> different from B, N is non-empty<br />

<strong>and</strong> countable.<br />

The accessibility relation on possible worlds is def<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

by <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g condition. Let w = ,<br />

w' = . Rww' if <strong>and</strong> only if both: (i) N is a<br />

proper subset of N', (ii) <strong>the</strong> restriction of d' to N (i.e.<br />

<strong>the</strong> set of those d'-related pairs whose first elements<br />

belong to N) is d.<br />

Let = w belong to W. A nam<strong>in</strong>g structure M = is w-complete if <strong>and</strong> only if: for any subset A of N<br />

<strong>the</strong>re exists a w’ = <strong>in</strong> M such that Rww' <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is an x <strong>in</strong> N' such that for any y <strong>in</strong> I, d'(x, y) if <strong>and</strong> only if y<br />

belongs to A. M is complete iff for any w <strong>in</strong> W, M is wcomplete.<br />

∆<br />

Def<strong>in</strong>ition. An M-<strong>in</strong>terpretation is a triple , where<br />

M is a nam<strong>in</strong>g structure, w = is a possible world <strong>in</strong><br />

M <strong>and</strong> v ei<strong>the</strong>r assigns to every variable <strong>in</strong> QNL an<br />

element of N, if N is non-empty, or is <strong>the</strong> empty function on<br />

<strong>the</strong> set of variables of QNL o<strong>the</strong>rwise. If M is a complete<br />

nam<strong>in</strong>g structure, <strong>the</strong>n we say that this M-<strong>in</strong>terpretation is<br />

complete. ∆<br />

Def<strong>in</strong>ition. Let be an M-<strong>in</strong>terpretation, w =<br />

. Also, let a <strong>and</strong> b be QNL-variables <strong>and</strong> A <strong>and</strong> B be<br />

QNL-formulas.<br />

models aεb iff v(a) <strong>and</strong> v(b) are def<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re exists a unique x <strong>in</strong> I such that is<br />

<strong>in</strong> d <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re is a y <strong>in</strong> I such that both <strong>and</strong><br />

are <strong>in</strong> d.<br />

The clauses for negation <strong>and</strong> conjunction are fairly<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard. A model models a negation iff v isn’t <strong>the</strong><br />

empty function <strong>and</strong> it doesn’t model <strong>the</strong> negated<br />

formula; <strong>and</strong> it models a conjunction iff it models<br />

both conjuncts.<br />

models (∃a)A iff for some w' <strong>in</strong> M, Rww'<br />

<strong>and</strong> models A, where v' differs from v at<br />

most <strong>in</strong> what it assigns to a.<br />

A sentence is true <strong>in</strong> a nam<strong>in</strong>g structure M if <strong>and</strong> only if it<br />

is satisfied <strong>in</strong> its bare world under any valuation. A sen-<br />

359

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!