02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Why <strong>the</strong> Phenomenal Concept Strategy Cannot Save Physicalism<br />

Mart<strong>in</strong>a Fürst, Graz, Austria<br />

I start elaborat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> phenomenal concept<br />

strategy concentrat<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> knowledge argument.<br />

Analyz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Mary-scenario <strong>the</strong> crucial particularities of<br />

phenomenal concepts are worked out. Next, I argue that<br />

only an <strong>in</strong>terpretation of phenomenal concepts which<br />

encapsulate <strong>the</strong>ir referents can capture <strong>the</strong> decisive<br />

uniqueness of <strong>the</strong>se concepts. F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>the</strong> defended<br />

account is compared with Pap<strong>in</strong>eau’s quotational account<br />

of phenomenal concepts. A careful analysis of this account<br />

shows that it has consequences which st<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> extreme<br />

contrast to <strong>the</strong> target <strong>the</strong> physicalist phenomenal<br />

conceptualist <strong>in</strong>tends to reach.<br />

1. The phenomenal concept strategy<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> most famous objections to Jackson’s knowledge<br />

argument (Jackson 1986) is <strong>the</strong> so-called two modes<br />

of presentation-reply. The basic idea of this reply – which<br />

is <strong>the</strong> possibility that one s<strong>in</strong>gle, ontological fact can be<br />

known under different modes of presentations – can be<br />

easily formulated on <strong>the</strong> level of concepts. This move<br />

leads to <strong>the</strong> notion of phenomenal concepts on <strong>the</strong> one<br />

h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion of physical concepts (understood <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> widest sense) on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>. These two sorts of<br />

concepts <strong>the</strong>n are treated <strong>in</strong> analogy to st<strong>and</strong>ard cases of<br />

co-reference. Hence, accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> two modes of presentation-reply<br />

<strong>the</strong> brilliant scientist Mary possessed all<br />

physical concepts, when be<strong>in</strong>g conf<strong>in</strong>ed to her achromatic<br />

room, but ga<strong>in</strong>ed new phenomenal ones, when enjoy<strong>in</strong>g<br />

her first colour-experience. Obviously, only type-Bmaterialist<br />

(Chalmers 1997), which grant that phenomenal<br />

concepts can not be a priori deduced from physical concepts,<br />

can adopt <strong>the</strong> physicalistic phenomenal concept<br />

strategy (Stoljar 2005). In o<strong>the</strong>r words: physicalists, who<br />

<strong>in</strong>tend to save an ontological materialism by grant<strong>in</strong>g just a<br />

conceptual or epistemic gap, developed this <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

of <strong>the</strong> knowledge argument to reach <strong>the</strong>ir target.<br />

The physicalist phenomenal concept strategy is<br />

based on <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> particularities of phenomenal<br />

concepts can expla<strong>in</strong> why one can not deduce <strong>the</strong>m a<br />

priori from physical concepts, although both sorts of concepts<br />

pick out one <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same ontological (ex hypo<strong>the</strong>si<br />

physical) referent. Hence, with regard to Mary it can be<br />

said that no metaphysical entities such as qualia have to<br />

be <strong>in</strong>voked to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> scientist’s new knowledge – it<br />

suffices to po<strong>in</strong>t out <strong>the</strong> uniqueness of phenomenal concepts.<br />

For this strategy to work, <strong>the</strong> decisive features of<br />

phenomenal concepts have to be elaborated. These particularities<br />

will have to expla<strong>in</strong> why phenomenal concepts<br />

are conceptually isolated (Carru<strong>the</strong>rs, Veillet 2007) from<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r concepts, but still pick out physical referents.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g I will demonstrate that if we take <strong>the</strong><br />

uniqueness of phenomenal concepts seriously, we have to<br />

conclude that <strong>the</strong>y refer to phenomenal entities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

<strong>the</strong> physicalist phenomenal concept strategy fails. I<br />

will start work<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>the</strong> crucial particularities of phenomenal<br />

concepts: one particularity concerns <strong>the</strong> conceptacquisition<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> very nature of such concepts.<br />

Importantly, both particularities of phenomenal concepts<br />

are such that <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>dicate phenomenal referents. In a<br />

second step, I will analyze one <strong>in</strong>terpretation of phenomenal<br />

concepts which seems to describe <strong>the</strong> crucial particu-<br />

106<br />

larities of <strong>the</strong>se concepts adequately: Pap<strong>in</strong>eau’s quotational<br />

account of phenomenal concepts (Pap<strong>in</strong>eau 2002,<br />

2007). A detailed exam<strong>in</strong>ation of this account will reveal<br />

two possible <strong>in</strong>terpretations: <strong>the</strong> first <strong>in</strong>terpretation is similar<br />

to <strong>the</strong> here<strong>in</strong> presented account <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore leads to<br />

a dualistic conclusion. The second <strong>in</strong>terpretation fails to<br />

expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> decisive features of phenomenal concepts;<br />

such as <strong>the</strong>ir semantic stability <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> closely l<strong>in</strong>ked fact<br />

of carry<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation about qualitative experiences.<br />

Hence, Pap<strong>in</strong>eau has to choose between accept<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

phenomenal concepts do refer to phenomenal referents or<br />

defend<strong>in</strong>g a view of phenomenal concepts which leave <strong>the</strong><br />

crucial particularities of phenomenal concepts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

also <strong>the</strong> Mary-scenario unexpla<strong>in</strong>ed.<br />

2. The encapsulation relation expla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong><br />

particularities of phenomenal concepts<br />

Let me start my <strong>in</strong>vestigation analyz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> particularities<br />

of phenomenal concepts. Regard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> conceptacquisition,<br />

<strong>the</strong> knowledge argument famously illustrated<br />

that we can ga<strong>in</strong> phenomenal concepts only under <strong>the</strong><br />

condition of attentively experienc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir referents. In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r words: one has to st<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> extraord<strong>in</strong>ary <strong>in</strong>timate<br />

relationship of acqua<strong>in</strong>tance with <strong>the</strong> referent a phenomenal<br />

concept picks out. Hence, when Mary leaves her<br />

achromatic environment, sees for <strong>the</strong> first time <strong>the</strong> blue sky<br />

<strong>and</strong> is attentively aware of this colour-experience, she<br />

ga<strong>in</strong>s a new phenomenal concept. Let me expla<strong>in</strong> this<br />

process <strong>in</strong> more detail: <strong>the</strong> brilliant scientist, who is aware<br />

of her very first blue-experience, discrim<strong>in</strong>ates this experience<br />

from all o<strong>the</strong>r current experiences. In my op<strong>in</strong>ion it is<br />

this act of attentive discrim<strong>in</strong>ation which immediately yields<br />

a concept referr<strong>in</strong>g to this particular, isolated experience.<br />

The close l<strong>in</strong>k between an experience <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ga<strong>in</strong>ed conception<br />

of it is a crucial po<strong>in</strong>t for my fur<strong>the</strong>r argumentation.<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> nature of phenomenal concepts, a<br />

careful analysis reveals an encapsulation relation between<br />

<strong>the</strong>se concepts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> referents <strong>the</strong>y pick out. The notion<br />

of an encapsulation relation can be considered as fundamental<br />

for <strong>the</strong> presented account. It is based on <strong>the</strong> idea<br />

that <strong>the</strong> experience itself is <strong>the</strong> core of <strong>the</strong> phenomenal<br />

concept referr<strong>in</strong>g to it. This fact can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong><br />

special way of ga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se concepts: when Mary discrim<strong>in</strong>ates<br />

a new experience she is acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with, this<br />

process of isolation implies giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> experience itself a<br />

conceptual structure <strong>and</strong> hence form<strong>in</strong>g a phenomenal<br />

concept which encapsulates <strong>the</strong> very experience itself.<br />

Obviously accord<strong>in</strong>g to this account, both <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> referent are occurrences <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject’s m<strong>in</strong>d. The<br />

<strong>in</strong>timate l<strong>in</strong>k of encapsulation of <strong>the</strong> referent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

has very particular roots <strong>and</strong> consequences:<br />

One crucial root of <strong>the</strong> encapsulation is <strong>the</strong> selfpresent<strong>in</strong>g<br />

character of <strong>the</strong> referent, which enables <strong>the</strong><br />

direct reference of <strong>the</strong> concept. It is precisely <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

an experience is self-present<strong>in</strong>g, i.e. that it serves as its<br />

own presentation, which is responsible for our acqua<strong>in</strong>tance<br />

<strong>and</strong> discrim<strong>in</strong>ative awareness of it <strong>and</strong> hence po<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

towards <strong>the</strong> close l<strong>in</strong>k between experience <strong>and</strong> phenomenal<br />

concept.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!