02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

These two conditions differ from (Pu1) <strong>and</strong> (Pu2) <strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

respect only: <strong>the</strong>y conta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> term ‘trope’ where<br />

(Pu1) <strong>and</strong> (Pu2) conta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> term ‘universal’. If (Pu1) <strong>and</strong><br />

(Pu2) lead to a regress, <strong>the</strong>n (Pt1) <strong>and</strong> (Pt2) equally lead to<br />

a regress. Instead of speak<strong>in</strong>g of universals or tropes, we<br />

can also formulate <strong>the</strong> matter <strong>in</strong> general terms, yield<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g pair of conditions:<br />

(P1) Wherever an entity is <strong>in</strong>stantiated, <strong>the</strong>re is an<br />

<strong>in</strong>stantiation relation (not identical to one of <strong>the</strong> relata).<br />

(P2) The <strong>in</strong>stantiation relation is an entity.<br />

The regress argument poses a threat only to those who<br />

are committed to <strong>the</strong>se two conditions. The trope <strong>the</strong>orist<br />

may deny (P2) as little as <strong>the</strong> realist. He will underst<strong>and</strong><br />

‘entity’ as referr<strong>in</strong>g to tropes because he is committed to<br />

<strong>the</strong> view that all relations are particularised relations,<br />

hence tropes. A difference between trope <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> realism<br />

concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se conditions can thus at most be given<br />

by a difference <strong>in</strong> commitment to (P1). It will now be shown<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re is no such difference.<br />

To see this, we must locate <strong>the</strong> motivation for (P1),<br />

<strong>the</strong> condition that <strong>in</strong>stantiation dem<strong>and</strong>s an <strong>in</strong>stantiation<br />

relation. In my view, <strong>the</strong> motivation lies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lack of a<br />

strict supervenience relation between <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong><br />

relata of <strong>in</strong>stantiation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stantiation itself: given a <strong>and</strong> F,<br />

it is not determ<strong>in</strong>ed that a <strong>in</strong>stantiates F. To illustrate this<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t, consider <strong>the</strong> situation <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>re are exactly four<br />

entities, particulars a <strong>and</strong> b <strong>and</strong> properties F <strong>and</strong> G. If we<br />

assume that both a <strong>and</strong> b <strong>in</strong>dividually <strong>and</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>gently<br />

<strong>in</strong>stantiate exactly one of <strong>the</strong> properties F <strong>and</strong> G, <strong>and</strong><br />

noth<strong>in</strong>g else, <strong>and</strong> if we assume that both F <strong>and</strong> G<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividually are (cont<strong>in</strong>gently) <strong>in</strong>stantiated by exactly one of<br />

<strong>the</strong> objects a <strong>and</strong> b, <strong>and</strong> by noth<strong>in</strong>g else, <strong>the</strong>n two<br />

situations are possible:<br />

W1: a <strong>in</strong>stantiates F; b <strong>in</strong>stantiates G.<br />

W2: a <strong>in</strong>stantiates G; b <strong>in</strong>stantiates F.<br />

Both situations comprise exactly <strong>the</strong> same particulars <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> same properties. Still, <strong>the</strong> situations differ; <strong>the</strong>y comprise<br />

different facts, different <strong>in</strong>stantiations. This means<br />

that <strong>the</strong> mere existence of particulars <strong>and</strong> properties does<br />

not necessitate a specific <strong>in</strong>stantiation. The mere existence<br />

of <strong>the</strong> car <strong>and</strong> blackness does not necessitate that <strong>the</strong> car<br />

is black. It may still be that <strong>the</strong> car is green, <strong>and</strong> what is<br />

black is <strong>the</strong> bike. The existence of particulars <strong>and</strong> properties<br />

may determ<strong>in</strong>e that facts <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stantiations obta<strong>in</strong>, as<br />

some authors (<strong>in</strong> particular Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> 1922 4 <strong>and</strong> Armstrong<br />

1997) ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>. But it does not determ<strong>in</strong>e which<br />

facts, which <strong>in</strong>stantiations obta<strong>in</strong>. As a recent author sums<br />

up this po<strong>in</strong>t:<br />

100<br />

Even if a <strong>and</strong> F-ness cannot exist except <strong>in</strong> some<br />

state of affairs or o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>re is noth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature<br />

of a <strong>and</strong> noth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature of F-ness to require<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y comb<strong>in</strong>e with each o<strong>the</strong>r to form a’s be<strong>in</strong>g F.<br />

(Valicella 2000, p. 238)<br />

Instantiation between two entities does not strictly supervene<br />

on <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong> entities alone, if <strong>the</strong>se entities<br />

are considered to be cont<strong>in</strong>gently related. We need more<br />

than <strong>the</strong> relata of <strong>in</strong>stantiation. This need is expressed by<br />

condition (P1). (P1) is <strong>the</strong> reaction to cont<strong>in</strong>gent <strong>in</strong>stantia-<br />

4 Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> makes this claim with <strong>the</strong> help of <strong>the</strong> notion of <strong>in</strong>completeness,<br />

which he borrows from Frege (1994/1892) but which he applies to all ‘objects’,<br />

properties <strong>and</strong> particulars alike. Toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>in</strong>complete objects<br />

cannot exist on <strong>the</strong>ir own, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> arrives at his famous view that “[t]he<br />

world is <strong>the</strong> totality of facts, not of objects” (Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> 1922, 1.1).<br />

Does Bradley’s Regress Support Nom<strong>in</strong>alism? — Wolfgang Freitag<br />

tion. The properties F <strong>and</strong> G <strong>in</strong> my example can be understood<br />

both as tropes <strong>and</strong> as universals. 5 It follows that,<br />

given cont<strong>in</strong>gent <strong>in</strong>stantiation, <strong>the</strong> trope <strong>the</strong>orist is as much<br />

committed to (P1) as <strong>the</strong> realist is. David Armstrong has<br />

seen this very clearly:<br />

Suppose that <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>k between a particular <strong>and</strong> its<br />

tropes is not necessary. Then it is cont<strong>in</strong>gent. But if<br />

it’s cont<strong>in</strong>gent, <strong>the</strong>n it seems that we have a clear<br />

case of a relation between a particular <strong>and</strong> its trope,<br />

<strong>and</strong> an external relation at that. But <strong>the</strong>n a Bradleian<br />

regress ensues […]. (Armstrong 2006, p. 242)<br />

This concludes <strong>the</strong> argument for my first claim: realism is<br />

no more committed to Bradley’s regress than at least one<br />

form of nom<strong>in</strong>alism, namely trope <strong>the</strong>ory. I now proceed to<br />

<strong>the</strong> argument for my second claim: nei<strong>the</strong>r position is<br />

committed to <strong>the</strong> regress.<br />

2. How to avoid Bradley’s regress<br />

2.1 Avoid<strong>in</strong>g commitment to (P1)<br />

Cont<strong>in</strong>gent <strong>in</strong>stantiation leads to (P1) <strong>and</strong> starts <strong>the</strong> regress.<br />

In order to avoid (P1), avoid cont<strong>in</strong>gent <strong>in</strong>stantiation.<br />

Make <strong>in</strong>stantiation necessary. There is a variety of<br />

different positions, both nom<strong>in</strong>alist <strong>and</strong> realist, which conceive<br />

of <strong>in</strong>stantiation as be<strong>in</strong>g necessary <strong>and</strong> hence avoid<br />

– <strong>in</strong>tentionally or not – commitment to (P1):<br />

(1) One position that makes <strong>in</strong>stantiation necessary<br />

is class nom<strong>in</strong>alism. This position, proposed <strong>in</strong>ter alia by<br />

Anthony Qu<strong>in</strong>ton (1957), underst<strong>and</strong>s hav<strong>in</strong>g a property as<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g a member of a certa<strong>in</strong> class of particulars. The<br />

object a <strong>in</strong>stantiates F iff a is a member of <strong>the</strong> F-class.<br />

Because classes are identified by <strong>the</strong>ir members <strong>and</strong><br />

class-membership is a necessary relation, <strong>in</strong>stantiation<br />

between a <strong>and</strong> F strictly supervenes on <strong>the</strong> existence of<br />

<strong>the</strong> F-class alone. In this way, class nom<strong>in</strong>alism can<br />

avoid (P1) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby <strong>the</strong> regress. Class nom<strong>in</strong>alism<br />

naturally escapes (P1).<br />

(2) Trope <strong>the</strong>ory also has its means of<br />

avoid<strong>in</strong>g (P1). In fact, a trope <strong>the</strong>orist has two options:<br />

(2a) Trope <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with a bundle <strong>the</strong>ory of<br />

particulars, as defended by, e.g., John Locke <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> more<br />

modern times, by D. C. Williams (1953), holds that<br />

particulars are sets or bundles of tropes. Consequently,<br />

a <strong>in</strong>stantiates F iff <strong>the</strong> F-trope is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> a-bundle. S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong><br />

identity of <strong>the</strong> a-bundle is, I take it, def<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong><br />

constitut<strong>in</strong>g tropes, a’s <strong>in</strong>stantiat<strong>in</strong>g F strictly supervenes<br />

on <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong> a-bundle. (2b) The second type of<br />

trope <strong>the</strong>ory comb<strong>in</strong>es a subject–attribute view with <strong>the</strong><br />

doctr<strong>in</strong>e of nontransferable tropes. A recent proponent of<br />

this view is John Heil (2003, chs. 12 <strong>and</strong> 13), although he<br />

prefers <strong>the</strong> term ‘mode’ to <strong>the</strong> term ‘trope’. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

this position, a trope is <strong>in</strong>stantiated by <strong>the</strong> very same<br />

object <strong>in</strong> all possible worlds. Given <strong>the</strong> nontransferable<br />

trope F <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular a, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>stantiation between<br />

a <strong>and</strong> F follows by necessity. 6 Aga<strong>in</strong> (P1) can be avoided.<br />

5 That F <strong>and</strong> G, understood as universals, are, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case discussed, <strong>in</strong>stantiated<br />

only by a s<strong>in</strong>gle entity, is not of relevance here. To see this, simply<br />

change <strong>the</strong> example accord<strong>in</strong>gly.<br />

6 This is simplified. There are at least three conceptions of <strong>the</strong> nontransferability<br />

of tropes: (i) F is <strong>in</strong>stantiated <strong>in</strong> all possible worlds, <strong>and</strong> it is<br />

<strong>in</strong>stantiated <strong>in</strong> all possible worlds by a. This presumably implies that a must<br />

exist <strong>in</strong> all possible worlds. (ii) F is not <strong>in</strong>stantiated <strong>in</strong> all possible worlds, but<br />

where it is, it is <strong>in</strong>stantiated by a. Option (ii) comes <strong>in</strong> two varieties: (a) <strong>in</strong> those<br />

worlds <strong>in</strong> which F is not <strong>in</strong>stantiated, a does not exist; (b) <strong>in</strong> some worlds <strong>in</strong><br />

which F is not <strong>in</strong>stantiated, a does exist. The supervenience claim <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong><br />

text holds only for (i) <strong>and</strong> (ii.a).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!