02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

(2) One-way Nagelian bridge pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. It has also<br />

been suggested that <strong>the</strong> common anti-reductionist<br />

argument <strong>in</strong>volves a misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> Nagelian<br />

model: although Nagel’s examples <strong>in</strong>volve biconditional<br />

bridge laws, one-way conditional connections express<strong>in</strong>g<br />

sufficient conditions at <strong>the</strong> reduc<strong>in</strong>g level are all that his<br />

“pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of derivability” requires. Multiple realizability, on<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, only challenges necessity reduc<strong>in</strong>g<br />

conditions, <strong>and</strong> so is not a challenge to even a projected<br />

Nagelian reduction of psychology to <strong>the</strong> physical sciences<br />

(Richardson 1979; cf. Bickle 2000). However, this<br />

approach is <strong>in</strong> considerable tension with <strong>the</strong> first objection<br />

to <strong>the</strong> Nagelian model, which requires that <strong>the</strong> connections<br />

between <strong>the</strong> reduced <strong>the</strong>ory T1 <strong>and</strong> reduc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory T2<br />

must be streng<strong>the</strong>ned, not weakened. Also, this strategy is<br />

<strong>in</strong> conflict with <strong>the</strong> exclusion argument: mere one-way<br />

conditionals simply won’t do; only genu<strong>in</strong>e identities<br />

suffice. O<strong>the</strong>rwise <strong>the</strong> mental (even if it may be “reducible”)<br />

may end up be<strong>in</strong>g causally epiphenomenal.<br />

(3) Reduced <strong>the</strong>ories are often false. Still ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

problem for <strong>the</strong> Nagelian model is presented by <strong>the</strong><br />

undeniable historical fact that often <strong>the</strong> reduced <strong>the</strong>ory T1<br />

is, strictly speak<strong>in</strong>g, false, <strong>and</strong> hence its laws can be<br />

derived from <strong>the</strong> reduc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory T2 (which is assumed, for<br />

<strong>the</strong> time be<strong>in</strong>g, to be true) only with some false auxiliary<br />

assumptions, for example. This holds even for many<br />

classical examples of reduction <strong>in</strong> science. Consequently,<br />

it has been proposed that what one really reduces (e.g.,<br />

derives from T2) is a revised version of T1 (or its “image” <strong>in</strong><br />

T2) ra<strong>the</strong>r than T1 itself (Schaffner 1967; Churchl<strong>and</strong><br />

1986).<br />

Yet, this observation poses no serious problems for<br />

<strong>the</strong> anti-reductionist; she need not commit herself to any<br />

specific <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g mental states (<strong>in</strong>deed, it is not<br />

even clear that <strong>the</strong>re exists a def<strong>in</strong>ite <strong>the</strong>ory of <strong>the</strong> mental<br />

that would be at stake here). She can well allow extensive<br />

correct<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong>ories. The real question here is about<br />

ontological reduction of properties, not about<br />

epistemological reduction of any particular <strong>the</strong>ory. (For this<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction, see Silberste<strong>in</strong> 2002.)<br />

(4) Local reductions. F<strong>in</strong>ally, it has been argued that<br />

<strong>the</strong> Nagelian condition of connectibility is “unrealistic <strong>and</strong><br />

can seldom be satisfied” (Kim 1998), <strong>and</strong> that even <strong>in</strong><br />

many paradigmatic examples of reduction <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> history of<br />

science <strong>the</strong> reduced concept is multiply realizable; e.g.,<br />

that temperature cannot be uniformly identified with a s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

micro-based property; it may be mean k<strong>in</strong>etic energy of<br />

molecules for gases, but someth<strong>in</strong>g else for solids or <strong>in</strong><br />

vacuums; but one may still have “local reductions” which<br />

are specific to doma<strong>in</strong>, structure or species – for example<br />

of temperature <strong>in</strong> gas, or, pa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> humans (Hooker 1981,<br />

Enc 1983, Churchl<strong>and</strong> 1986, Ch. 7, Kim 1998, Bickle<br />

2000).<br />

However, this strategy too faces problems <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

presence of <strong>the</strong> exclusion argument: toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y<br />

threaten to make <strong>the</strong> general property of pa<strong>in</strong> but also of<br />

temperature causally epiphenomenal (see below). And <strong>in</strong><br />

any case, this k<strong>in</strong>d of reply may well be <strong>in</strong>sufficient: one<br />

may argue for a much more radical type of multiple<br />

realizability, that <strong>the</strong> underly<strong>in</strong>g physical realizations of a<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> psychological property may differ even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> one<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same token <strong>in</strong>dividual over time (Block 1978,<br />

Horgan 1993). Arguably <strong>the</strong>re is some empirical evidence<br />

about such plasticity (Endicott 1993). Yet, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of<br />

The Return of Reductive Physicalism — Panu Raatika<strong>in</strong>en<br />

such a massive k<strong>in</strong>d of multiple realizability, <strong>the</strong> idea of<br />

local reduction leads to absurdity. At least one key<br />

advocate of new wave reductionism, John Bickle, grants<br />

this much: “The more radical type of multiple realizability<br />

seems to force <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly narrower doma<strong>in</strong>s for<br />

reductions to be relativized – at <strong>the</strong> extreme, to <strong>in</strong>dividuals<br />

at times. This much ‘local reduction’ seems <strong>in</strong>consistent<br />

with <strong>the</strong> assumed generality of science” (Bickle 2006).<br />

5. A <strong>Reduction</strong>ist Reply to Radical Multiple<br />

Realizability<br />

Bickle – follow<strong>in</strong>g Hooker (1981) <strong>and</strong> Enc (1983) – argues<br />

that <strong>the</strong> radical type of multiple realizability is a feature of<br />

some “textbook” cases of reduction, such as <strong>the</strong> one of<br />

classical <strong>the</strong>rmodynamics to statistical mechanics: “For<br />

any token aggregate of gas molecules, <strong>the</strong>re is an <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

number of realizations of a given temperature – a<br />

given mean molecular k<strong>in</strong>etic energy. Microphysically, <strong>the</strong><br />

most f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>oretical specification of a gas is its<br />

microcanonical ensemble, <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> momentum <strong>and</strong><br />

location (<strong>and</strong> thus <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>etic energy) of each molecule are<br />

specified. Indef<strong>in</strong>itely many dist<strong>in</strong>ct microcanonical ensembles<br />

of a token volume of gas molecules can yield <strong>the</strong><br />

same mean molecular k<strong>in</strong>etic energy. Thus at <strong>the</strong> lowest<br />

level of microphysical description, a given temperature is<br />

vastly multiply realizable <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same token system over<br />

times … So this type of multiple realizability is not by itself<br />

a barrier to reducibility” (Bickle 2006).<br />

To beg<strong>in</strong> with, a “textbook case” or not, one should<br />

note that some dist<strong>in</strong>guished philosophers of physics have<br />

expressed serious doubts about this alleged reduction of<br />

classical <strong>the</strong>rmodynamics. The locality of it mentioned<br />

above is actually one of <strong>the</strong> reasons, but <strong>the</strong>re are many<br />

more: for example, statistical mechanics is time symmetric<br />

whereas <strong>the</strong>rmodynamics possesses time asymmetry<br />

(Primas 1991, 1998, Sklar 1993, 1999; cf. Silberste<strong>in</strong><br />

2002). So perhaps one should not make too much out of<br />

<strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>gent fact that Nagel <strong>and</strong> some o<strong>the</strong>rs took this as<br />

a good example of reduction.<br />

Moreover, this strategy has its price; now <strong>the</strong><br />

exclusion argument enters, <strong>and</strong> one must conclude aga<strong>in</strong><br />

that temperature is a causally epiphenomenal property.<br />

For, temperature clearly is not identical to any particular<br />

token microlevel arrangement or such. 1 But without<br />

genu<strong>in</strong>e identities, one cannot circumvent <strong>the</strong> exclusion<br />

problem. And surely, <strong>the</strong> conclusion is implausible. For<br />

example, consider water boil<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a test tube. Now <strong>the</strong><br />

difference-mak<strong>in</strong>g cause of <strong>the</strong> boil<strong>in</strong>g is seem<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>the</strong><br />

temperature (> 100°C) of its surround<strong>in</strong>gs, no matter<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r it was solid or gas, <strong>and</strong> whatever its specific<br />

arrangement of microparticles is. Therefore, someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

must have gone wrong.<br />

6. Conclusions<br />

Advances <strong>in</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g reduction <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophy of<br />

science must certa<strong>in</strong>ly be taken <strong>in</strong>to account. However,<br />

arguably <strong>the</strong>y are not as much help to reductive physicalism<br />

as is sometimes suggested. In particular, contemporary<br />

physicalism which essentially depends on <strong>the</strong> exclusion<br />

problem does not harmonize well with certa<strong>in</strong> new<br />

views of reductionism.<br />

1 As Tim Crane po<strong>in</strong>ted out <strong>in</strong> a discussion, essentially <strong>the</strong> same worry is<br />

already presented (<strong>in</strong> a slightly different context) <strong>in</strong> Crane (1992).<br />

269

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!