02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

How do Moral Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples Figure <strong>in</strong> Moral Judgement?<br />

A Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>ian Contribution to <strong>the</strong> Particularism Debate<br />

Matthias Kiesselbach, Potsdam, Germany<br />

1. Introduction: What is moral deliberation?<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> key debates <strong>in</strong> current moral philosophy focuses<br />

on <strong>the</strong> role of moral pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> moral deliberation.<br />

Among <strong>the</strong> many op<strong>in</strong>ions on <strong>the</strong> table, we f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ses<br />

of Universal Weak Particularism (UWP) <strong>and</strong> Universal<br />

Weak Generalism (UWG), which can be formulated as<br />

follows:<br />

172<br />

(UWP) Generally, <strong>the</strong> application of moral pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<br />

is not sufficient for correct moral judgement.<br />

(UWG) Generally, <strong>the</strong> application of moral pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<br />

is necessary for correct moral judgement.<br />

Obviously, <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>ses are mutually consistent. Moreover,<br />

both are conclusions of strong arguments: (UWP) is<br />

<strong>in</strong>ductively supported by <strong>the</strong> fact that, so far, for every<br />

c<strong>and</strong>idate of a suitably general <strong>and</strong> non-trivial moral pr<strong>in</strong>ciple,<br />

it has been possible to devise a scenario <strong>in</strong> which<br />

<strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple's strict application would strike us as simply<br />

wrong. This is true for both all out <strong>and</strong> pro tanto pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<br />

(see Dancy 2004). (UWG) is supported by <strong>the</strong> fact that our<br />

aim of consistency <strong>in</strong> ethical learn<strong>in</strong>g, debate <strong>and</strong> judgement<br />

is not just a piece of ideology, but an actually atta<strong>in</strong>able<br />

goal. Consistency between particular moral judgements,<br />

however, is noth<strong>in</strong>g but <strong>the</strong> existence of pr<strong>in</strong>cipled<br />

relations among <strong>the</strong>m. If <strong>the</strong>se arguments are successful,<br />

we have good reason to accept both (UWP) <strong>and</strong> (UWG).<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation of (UWP) <strong>and</strong> (UWG)<br />

does not seem to appeal to many commentators. Their<br />

reservation is, I th<strong>in</strong>k, due to <strong>the</strong> thought that we lack a<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory of moral deliberation which implies both <strong>the</strong>ses at<br />

once. What are moral pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, <strong>the</strong>y ask, if moral<br />

judgement cannot be reduced to <strong>the</strong>ir application, <strong>and</strong> yet<br />

depends on <strong>the</strong> latter? In this paper, I want to argue that<br />

<strong>the</strong> work of <strong>the</strong> later (<strong>and</strong> latest) Ludwig Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> gives<br />

rise to an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> plausible answer to this question.<br />

It revolves around <strong>the</strong> ideas that moral pr<strong>in</strong>ciples can be<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpreted as grammatical propositions, <strong>and</strong> that moral<br />

problems can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as <strong>in</strong>stances of grammatical<br />

<strong>in</strong>consistency <strong>and</strong>, hence, as occasions for grammatical<br />

revision. Moral judgement, on this view, is a matter of<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g grammar, but it is also a matter of adequately<br />

revis<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> face of grammatical tension.<br />

2. Grammatical statements, grammatical<br />

tension <strong>and</strong> grammatical evolution <strong>in</strong><br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>'s work<br />

We are surely warranted to take seriously Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>'s<br />

<strong>in</strong>sistence that his project is one of philosophical <strong>the</strong>rapy,<br />

aim<strong>in</strong>g to free us from our urge to philosophise by unmask<strong>in</strong>g<br />

our seem<strong>in</strong>gly deep metaphysical ideas as mere<br />

grammatical confusions. However, <strong>in</strong> order to be able to<br />

read Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> this way, we cannot help but ascribe<br />

to him a certa<strong>in</strong> number of <strong>the</strong>oretical commitments regard<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>gs of language. In this section, I want to<br />

review, as quickly as possible, key elements of Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>'s<br />

mature conception of language, <strong>and</strong> to show that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y comprise ideas of grammatical tension <strong>and</strong> grammatical<br />

evolution.<br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>'s return to philosophy <strong>in</strong> 1929 marks a<br />

radicalisation of <strong>the</strong> view that natural language is best<br />

analysed as a practical calculus embedded <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

cont<strong>in</strong>uous with non-l<strong>in</strong>guistic practice. While <strong>the</strong> Tractatus<br />

still enterta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> idea that some (namely <strong>the</strong> “atomic”)<br />

propositions st<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> isomorphic relations with aspects of<br />

<strong>the</strong> world, <strong>the</strong> later Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> th<strong>in</strong>ks of <strong>the</strong> calculus of<br />

language as fully autonomous. All utterances are now<br />

conceived as practical manoeuvres, connected via rules<br />

with o<strong>the</strong>r such manoeuvres as well as with non-l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

phenomena <strong>and</strong> do<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir vic<strong>in</strong>ity. On this view, all<br />

talk of “mean<strong>in</strong>g” or “content” is just a way of discuss<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> role which an expression plays with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical<br />

calculus of language.<br />

This idea poses an obvious threat to <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

between analytic <strong>and</strong> empirical content. Traditionally, <strong>the</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g of a proposition was thought to be a twocomponent<br />

object. There was <strong>the</strong> empirical component on<br />

<strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> analytical (logical, conceptual)<br />

component on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. With <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

an expression is exhausted by <strong>the</strong> logical or, as<br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> has it: <strong>in</strong>ternal (TLP 4.125ff., 5.131, 5.2ff.)<br />

role with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> calculus, it becomes an open question how<br />

empirical content is at all possible, or what it would amount<br />

to.<br />

Moreover, <strong>in</strong> attack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> traditional analyticempirical<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>'s move threatens our<br />

everyday practice of dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g between<br />

misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> disagreement. If communication, as<br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> writes, depends on “agreement not only <strong>in</strong><br />

def<strong>in</strong>itions but also (queer as this may sound) <strong>in</strong><br />

judgements” (PI 242), <strong>the</strong>n it seems that every time<br />

speakers diverge <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir propositional judgements, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

turn out to play different games <strong>and</strong> thus talk past each<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r. Can this be true?<br />

While many th<strong>in</strong>kers have taken this threat as a<br />

pure <strong>and</strong> simple reductio ad absurdum, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> holds<br />

fast to his <strong>in</strong>terpretation of language as a practical calculus<br />

<strong>and</strong> looks, <strong>in</strong> his later writ<strong>in</strong>gs, for a pragmatic way to reerect<br />

<strong>the</strong> traditional dist<strong>in</strong>ctions <strong>in</strong> question. Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>'s<br />

eventual solution centres around <strong>the</strong> idea that if<br />

philosophers took <strong>in</strong>to account ord<strong>in</strong>ary speaker's actual<br />

employment of <strong>the</strong> calculus of language, <strong>the</strong>y would soon<br />

notice that speakers do not just draw on its rules, but<br />

constantly develop <strong>the</strong>m fur<strong>the</strong>r. They are always, he<br />

th<strong>in</strong>ks, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess of co<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g new l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

manoeuvres, such as new propositions. Of course, it has<br />

long been known that our language is compositional. i.e.<br />

that it comprises sub-propositional components (such as<br />

concepts) which can be regrouped to form new, yet<br />

immediately underst<strong>and</strong>able, sentences (<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

utterances). But s<strong>in</strong>ce concept rules are, on a calculus<br />

account of language, bound up with proposition rules, this<br />

does not show how empirical content or <strong>the</strong> possibility of<br />

proper disagreement comes <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> picture. Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>'s<br />

idea, now, is that we can use propositions to alter <strong>the</strong> rules<br />

govern<strong>in</strong>g concepts – i.e. <strong>the</strong>ir mean<strong>in</strong>gs – <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

convey empirical content.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!