02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Two <strong>Reduction</strong>s of ‘rule’<br />

Dana Riesenfeld, Tel Aviv, Israel<br />

1. First reduction: The reduction of rules to<br />

conventions 1<br />

Kripke (1982) sees Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s discussion on rule follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

as present<strong>in</strong>g a paradox which br<strong>in</strong>gs about a skeptical<br />

conclusion: “..<strong>the</strong>re is no fact about me that dist<strong>in</strong>guishes<br />

my mean<strong>in</strong>g a def<strong>in</strong>ite function by ‘+’ …<strong>and</strong> my<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g noth<strong>in</strong>g at all” (1982: 21). But as this “skeptical<br />

[sic.] 2 conclusion is <strong>in</strong>sane <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tolerable” (1982: 60),<br />

Kripke attempts to solve <strong>the</strong> it by offer<strong>in</strong>g a skeptical conclusion<br />

that <strong>in</strong>volves an appeal to community, <strong>and</strong> which<br />

has later been entitled ‘<strong>the</strong> community view’. The outcome<br />

of <strong>the</strong> paradox is that words do not have pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs, however, he argues, <strong>the</strong>y do ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

by <strong>the</strong> rule’s tendency to match <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir usage with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

l<strong>in</strong>guistic community. Mean<strong>in</strong>gs are not derivative of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

conform<strong>in</strong>g to rules but ra<strong>the</strong>r derive from <strong>the</strong>ir compliance<br />

with a social consensus regard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir proper or correct<br />

use: “<strong>the</strong> community must be able to judge whe<strong>the</strong>r an<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual is <strong>in</strong>deed follow<strong>in</strong>g a given rule <strong>in</strong> particular applications,<br />

i.e. whe<strong>the</strong>r his responses agree with our own”<br />

(1982: 109).<br />

The first chapter of Kripke’s book (“The<br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>ian paradox” pp. 22-37) consists <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

attempts of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terlocutor to oppose <strong>the</strong> skeptic’s doubts<br />

concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of ‘+’, <strong>the</strong> addition sign. The<br />

skeptic casts doubt on whe<strong>the</strong>r anyth<strong>in</strong>g at all (not<br />

exclusively a rule) can establish mean<strong>in</strong>g. Hav<strong>in</strong>g been<br />

persuaded by <strong>the</strong> skeptic’s arguments that <strong>the</strong>re is no fact<br />

about me which ensures my mean<strong>in</strong>g ‘plus’ ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

‘quus’, Kripke exam<strong>in</strong>es a few plausible answers to <strong>the</strong><br />

skeptic, devot<strong>in</strong>g most of his efforts to reject <strong>the</strong><br />

dispositional account as an <strong>in</strong>adequate account of rule<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Dispositionalism <strong>in</strong> this context is <strong>the</strong> idea that “To<br />

mean addition by ‘+’ is to be disposed to, when asked for<br />

any sum ‘x+y’, to give <strong>the</strong> sum of x <strong>and</strong> y as <strong>the</strong> answer …<br />

to mean quus is to be disposed, when queried about any<br />

arguments, to respond with <strong>the</strong>ir quum” (1982: 22-23). For<br />

Kripke it is very important to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between his<br />

position <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dispositionalist account. Kripke raises a<br />

few difficulties for <strong>the</strong> dispositionalist account, <strong>the</strong> most<br />

important of which is <strong>the</strong> claim that it aims to shed light on<br />

<strong>the</strong> normative practice of rule follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> descriptive<br />

terms.<br />

Dispositions tell us how we will answer not how we<br />

ought to answer. This po<strong>in</strong>t is stressed by Kripke<br />

throughout his attempts to dismiss <strong>the</strong> dispositional<br />

account as an adequate c<strong>and</strong>idate to answer <strong>the</strong> skeptic:<br />

Suppose I do mean addition by ‘+’. What is <strong>the</strong> relation<br />

of this supposition to <strong>the</strong> question how I will respond<br />

to <strong>the</strong> problem ’68 + 57’? The dispositionalist<br />

gives a descriptive account of this relation: if ‘+’<br />

meant addition, <strong>the</strong>n I will answer ‘125’. But this is<br />

1 Throughout, I refer to Kripke’s views, ignor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> question of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

view Kripke is assign<strong>in</strong>g to Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> is really his, whe<strong>the</strong>r it is Kripke’s<br />

position or whe<strong>the</strong>r it is a hybrid view sometimes assigned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature to<br />

‘Kripkenste<strong>in</strong>’. Kripke himself is unclear about this issue, (1982: 5).<br />

2 Throughout Kripke’s text ‘sceptic’ <strong>and</strong> ‘scepticism’ are spelled with a ‘C’.<br />

When quot<strong>in</strong>g, I left <strong>the</strong> spell<strong>in</strong>g as it appears <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al text.<br />

not <strong>the</strong> proper account of <strong>the</strong> relation which is normative,<br />

not descriptive. The po<strong>in</strong>t is not that, if I<br />

meant addition by ‘+’, I will answer ‘125’ but that, if I<br />

<strong>in</strong>tend to accord with my past mean<strong>in</strong>g of ‘+’ I<br />

should answer ‘125’… The relation of mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>tention to future action is normative, not descriptive<br />

(1982: 37).<br />

Kripke’s discussion of <strong>the</strong> dispositionalist account <strong>and</strong> his<br />

critique of it make it clear that any adequate explanation of<br />

‘rules’ must reta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> normative aspect of rules. But does<br />

Kripke’s own account give an explanation of rule follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> normative terms? In what follows, I claim it does not.<br />

Kripke’s skeptical solution is achieved by a<br />

‘widen<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> gaze’, “…from consideration of <strong>the</strong> rule<br />

follower alone <strong>and</strong> allow ourselves to consider him as<br />

<strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g with a wider community” (1982: 89). So <strong>in</strong><br />

answer to <strong>the</strong> question ‘what are rules?’ Kripke replies that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>and</strong> by <strong>the</strong>mselves noth<strong>in</strong>g at all.<br />

Only when thought about aga<strong>in</strong>st a background of <strong>the</strong><br />

community of speakers with<strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y operate <strong>the</strong>y<br />

have mean<strong>in</strong>g. The concept of rule means noth<strong>in</strong>g when<br />

abstracted from <strong>the</strong> use of rules by a community, <strong>and</strong> does<br />

not have any objective mean<strong>in</strong>g outside of how rules<br />

operate <strong>in</strong> actual speech. Rules of mean<strong>in</strong>g are thus rules<br />

of use, <strong>and</strong> correct, justified <strong>and</strong> guided use of rules is<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g that is <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple dependent upon <strong>the</strong><br />

pronouncement of <strong>the</strong> community of speakers.<br />

This idea is presented by <strong>the</strong> emphasis Kripke puts<br />

on <strong>the</strong> procedure he calls public checkability:<br />

“Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s sceptical solution to his problem depends<br />

on agreement, <strong>and</strong> on checkability – on one person’s<br />

ability to test whe<strong>the</strong>r ano<strong>the</strong>r uses a term as he does”<br />

(1982: 99). Public checkability, or agreement, now sets <strong>the</strong><br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard of correctness <strong>and</strong> replaces <strong>the</strong> appeal to <strong>the</strong><br />

rule as provid<strong>in</strong>g such st<strong>and</strong>ard.<br />

‘Agreement’ for Kripke is not an objective fact but it<br />

is a brute fact. It is not objective <strong>in</strong> a Platonic sense, for<br />

agreement can change <strong>and</strong> shift <strong>and</strong> what we agree on<br />

today may not be what we will agree upon tomorrow. It is<br />

<strong>in</strong> this sense that agreement lacks <strong>the</strong> necessitation of<br />

e.g., a law of nature. However, agreement is a brute fact, a<br />

descriptive notion, captur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> conventions <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

community abides by at a certa<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> time. In fact,<br />

Kripke claims, we do agree (e.g., on <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong><br />

addition sign) generally. But what does it mean to<br />

generally agree? Does it mean that most of us agree most<br />

of <strong>the</strong> time? That most of us agree part of <strong>the</strong> time?<br />

Perhaps that part of us agree all of <strong>the</strong> time? In o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

words, how do <strong>the</strong> concepts of agreement <strong>and</strong> public<br />

checkability differentiate between correct <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>correct rule<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> between those <strong>and</strong> not follow<strong>in</strong>g any rule at<br />

all?<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Kripke’s solution, when asked to justify<br />

an action (e.g., giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> answer 125 to <strong>the</strong> addition<br />

problem: 68+57) one should answer: “I gave this answer<br />

because everyone else does”. Follow<strong>in</strong>g a rule is found to<br />

be no more (<strong>and</strong> no less) than act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> conformity to<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs. The maxim “act like everyone else does” replaces<br />

<strong>the</strong> appeal to rules when one searches for justification. An<br />

important merit of this solution is that it ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s one of<br />

<strong>the</strong> most basic <strong>in</strong>tuitions about rules: <strong>the</strong>ir fallibility. Rules<br />

283

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!