02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Word-Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Context Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Investigations<br />

Jaime Nester, Blacksburg, Virg<strong>in</strong>ia, USA<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Investigations, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> suggests we should, “let<br />

<strong>the</strong> use of words teach (us) <strong>the</strong>ir mean<strong>in</strong>g” (Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>,<br />

2002, p.187). By draw<strong>in</strong>g our attention to use, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong><br />

believes we will see how our l<strong>in</strong>guistic practices confer<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g on words. Though this l<strong>in</strong>e of thought seems<br />

promis<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>re may yet be an issue concern<strong>in</strong>g how we<br />

come to underst<strong>and</strong> word-mean<strong>in</strong>g. To clarify how wordmean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

can derive from use, I will tie Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

notion of mean<strong>in</strong>g-as-use to Frege’s context pr<strong>in</strong>ciple; <strong>in</strong><br />

do<strong>in</strong>g this, I will show how Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> attributes a<br />

broader scope to <strong>the</strong> context pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that extends beyond<br />

mere propositions. I <strong>in</strong>tend to argue that Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g-as-use shows how Frege’s context pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is<br />

open to circularity, while his transformation of it is not. To<br />

make this argument, it will be necessary to expla<strong>in</strong> what<br />

Frege’s context pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is <strong>and</strong> to show how it operates <strong>in</strong><br />

conjunction with his o<strong>the</strong>r two guid<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. This<br />

explanation will enable me to show how Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

transformation of <strong>the</strong> context pr<strong>in</strong>ciple allows him to claim<br />

that our l<strong>in</strong>guistic practices confer mean<strong>in</strong>g upon words<br />

without open<strong>in</strong>g himself to circularity.<br />

Frege’s first guid<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is, “Always separate<br />

sharply <strong>the</strong> psychological from <strong>the</strong> logical, <strong>the</strong> subjective<br />

from <strong>the</strong> objective” (Frege, p.X). Frege believed arithmetic<br />

fell under <strong>the</strong> laws of logic <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> laws of logic<br />

govern all thought. Frege is not concerned with <strong>the</strong><br />

subjective mechanics of th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, but only with what is<br />

essential to thought <strong>in</strong> order that judgments have truthvalues;<br />

judgments have truth-values regardless of whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are ever thought by <strong>in</strong>dividuals (Frege, p.36-38). In<br />

contrast with psychology, logic is essentially a subject<br />

matter concerned with truth. Frege’s first guid<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

is aimed at show<strong>in</strong>g how logic furnishes <strong>the</strong> laws of<br />

thought, which makes possible <strong>the</strong> claims of truth <strong>in</strong> any<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r discipl<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g psychology (Frege, p.21).<br />

Frege’s second guid<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple (<strong>the</strong> context<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple), enjo<strong>in</strong>s us to ‘look for’ <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of a word<br />

only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of a proposition (Frege, p.X). While this<br />

formulation suggests <strong>the</strong> possibility that words may have<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> isolation, Frege none<strong>the</strong>less holds one cannot<br />

identify or judge <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of a word unless it is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

context of a proposition. At this po<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>the</strong> importance<br />

attributed to Frege’s context pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is that it helps one<br />

avoid violat<strong>in</strong>g his first guid<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Frege holds that if<br />

one takes a word <strong>in</strong> isolation, one may be tempted to take<br />

<strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of that word to be some idea (‘Vorstellung’)<br />

one associates with it. Later <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Grundlagen, Frege<br />

gives a much stronger formulation of <strong>the</strong> context pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

when he states words do not have a mean<strong>in</strong>g when taken<br />

<strong>in</strong> isolation (Frege, p.71). So, it is not that words have a<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g outside <strong>the</strong> context of a proposition, but ra<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

<strong>the</strong> proposition confers mean<strong>in</strong>g on words. Why is a<br />

proposition essential to word-mean<strong>in</strong>g? Why is it<br />

<strong>in</strong>essential that we have <strong>in</strong>tuitions associated with words?<br />

When one takes a proper name <strong>in</strong> isolation (e.g.,<br />

‘Tolstoy’), it states noth<strong>in</strong>g; it has no truth-value. Likewise,<br />

predicates (e.g., ‘wrote War <strong>and</strong> Peace) have no truthvalue<br />

by <strong>the</strong>mselves. In comb<strong>in</strong>ation, however, a name<br />

<strong>and</strong> predicate express a proposition that necessarily has a<br />

truth-value (e.g., ‘Tolstoy wrote War <strong>and</strong> Peace). The<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> components goes back to <strong>the</strong> contribution<br />

<strong>the</strong>y make to <strong>the</strong> truth-value of <strong>the</strong> proposition as a whole.<br />

244<br />

So, <strong>the</strong> name ‘Tolstoy’ ga<strong>in</strong>s its mean<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

it occurs <strong>in</strong> a proposition with a truth-value (i.e., <strong>the</strong><br />

proposition has a sense); whatever subjective impressions<br />

I have of Tolstoy are irrelevant to <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of ‘Tolstoy;’<br />

<strong>and</strong>, ‘Tolstoy’ cannot be placed toge<strong>the</strong>r with just any<br />

words to produce a proposition. For example, ‘Tolstoy<br />

Gottlob Frege’ does not express anyth<strong>in</strong>g. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, a name<br />

must be coupled with a predicate <strong>in</strong> order to produce a<br />

proposition. Why is this <strong>the</strong> case? Is Frege only draw<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

our grammatical knowledge of natural language <strong>in</strong><br />

assess<strong>in</strong>g what is requisite for a proposition with a sense?<br />

The grammatical categories of names <strong>and</strong><br />

predicates correspond to features of propositions that<br />

make a systematic contribution to <strong>the</strong> truth-value of a<br />

proposition. These features are <strong>the</strong>n logical categories that<br />

divide <strong>the</strong> essential logical components of a proposition.<br />

Names correspond to <strong>the</strong> logical category of ‘object,’<br />

predicates to ‘concept;’ <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of a name is <strong>the</strong><br />

object to which it refers, <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of a predicate <strong>the</strong><br />

concept it picks out. The crucial po<strong>in</strong>t, however, is that<br />

‘reference’ <strong>in</strong> both cases is derivative from <strong>the</strong> sense of <strong>the</strong><br />

proposition (Dummett, p.5). The reference of ‘Tolstoy’ to<br />

Tolstoy stems from <strong>the</strong> sign mak<strong>in</strong>g a contribution to <strong>the</strong><br />

sense of a proposition; this contribution shows <strong>the</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g of ‘Tolstoy.’ If ‘Tolstoy’ did not do that, it would be<br />

logically <strong>in</strong>ert, mean<strong>in</strong>gless. The name ‘Tolstoy’ contributes<br />

to <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of a proposition by pick<strong>in</strong>g out an object;<br />

<strong>the</strong> predicate names a concept <strong>and</strong> thus contributes to <strong>the</strong><br />

proposition by pick<strong>in</strong>g out a property to be asserted of that<br />

object. The object-concept coupl<strong>in</strong>g yields a full<br />

proposition; this calls us to Frege’s third guid<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple:<br />

“Always dist<strong>in</strong>guish between concept <strong>and</strong> object” (Frege,<br />

p.X). In some sense, this pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is an outgrowth of <strong>the</strong><br />

second because it tells us what, with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of a<br />

proposition, is essential to its hav<strong>in</strong>g a truth-value. On my<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation, Frege’s three guid<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples work <strong>in</strong><br />

concert to protect <strong>the</strong> logical values of propositions.<br />

Frege builds word-mean<strong>in</strong>g out of a l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

calculus that focuses on <strong>the</strong> truth-value of propositions,<br />

<strong>and</strong> this shows how truth-values derive from a<br />

proposition’s component parts. Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> takes issue<br />

with this view of mean<strong>in</strong>g because <strong>the</strong> components of<br />

propositions are words, <strong>and</strong> if words are to be used<br />

correctly, we must have some knowledge of <strong>the</strong>ir mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

if we are to use <strong>the</strong>m correctly. Frege h<strong>in</strong>ts at how this<br />

could be a plausible conception of mean<strong>in</strong>g when he<br />

claims, “<strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ition of an object does not really assert<br />

anyth<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> object, but only lays down <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of a symbol” (Frege, p.78). S<strong>in</strong>ce words operate as<br />

symbols of objects for Frege, it seems we could grasp <strong>the</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g of words by simply look<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong>ir def<strong>in</strong>itions.<br />

This calls our attention to Frege’s problem of circularity:<br />

<strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs of words are just more words that st<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

for <strong>the</strong>m (Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, 2002, p.12). Frege dist<strong>in</strong>guishes<br />

between sense <strong>and</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g, but it not possible for us to<br />

grasp <strong>the</strong> sense of a proposition without first know<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g of its constituent words. For Frege, grasp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

sense of a proposition is someth<strong>in</strong>g we ought not to<br />

question because it is a psychological matter; this is<br />

problematic because it suggests that <strong>the</strong> logic of grammar<br />

itself provides us with word-mean<strong>in</strong>g. For Frege, grasp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> sense of a proposition is supposed to lead us to <strong>the</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g of that proposition; but we cannot grasp <strong>the</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!