02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Transcendental <strong>Philosophy</strong> <strong>and</strong> M<strong>in</strong>d-Body <strong>Reduction</strong>ism — Christian Helmut Wenzel<br />

Doubt<strong>in</strong>g causality <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> way Hume did is mistaken<br />

<strong>in</strong> Kant’s eyes. We need an a priori concept of causality<br />

from <strong>the</strong> start to have any of <strong>the</strong> coherent experiences that<br />

we as a matter of fact do have. Particular empirical<br />

causalities can be learned about <strong>in</strong> experience, but not<br />

causality <strong>in</strong> general, universally, as such, which we need <strong>in</strong><br />

order to have any mean<strong>in</strong>gful experiences to start with.<br />

To have an apparently simple experience such as<br />

<strong>the</strong> perception of a ship, we need to see <strong>the</strong> ship as a unit,<br />

<strong>and</strong> for that we need <strong>the</strong> category of substance. That <strong>the</strong><br />

parts of <strong>the</strong> ship stay where <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>and</strong> do not float<br />

around chaotically <strong>and</strong> dissolve, <strong>and</strong> that I dist<strong>in</strong>guish <strong>the</strong><br />

ship from my perceiv<strong>in</strong>g it, presupposes a priori causality.<br />

Thus just to perceive a ship, without even <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

question of empirical causality by ask<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r it is<br />

go<strong>in</strong>g downstream or upstream, <strong>the</strong> categories are<br />

needed.<br />

Even deeper, it is I who perceives <strong>the</strong> ship <strong>and</strong> I am<br />

conscious of this act. It is I who gives it unity <strong>and</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> perception <strong>and</strong> judgment. Already here I do someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that requires a priori concepts. (For accounts of Kant on<br />

<strong>the</strong> I <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, <strong>the</strong> ‘unity of thought argument’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

‘<strong>in</strong>ner sense argument’, <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> complexities of various<br />

k<strong>in</strong>ds of immaterialism of <strong>the</strong> soul, see Ameriks 2000,<br />

especially pp. 27-47. For a defense of <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong><br />

categories go “all <strong>the</strong> way out”, see Wenzel 2005.)<br />

We might be tempted to see even <strong>the</strong>se a priori<br />

concepts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir application as be<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g mental<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>. After all, Kant th<strong>in</strong>ks of <strong>the</strong> categories as subjective.<br />

But <strong>the</strong> Kantian subject is not a m<strong>in</strong>d-bra<strong>in</strong> that is causally<br />

affected. In <strong>the</strong> framework of his transcendental<br />

epistemology, <strong>the</strong> subject even comprises time <strong>and</strong> space,<br />

as forms of all appearances. If we th<strong>in</strong>k of ourselves as<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g affected by th<strong>in</strong>gs “outside of us”, außer uns, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

<strong>the</strong>se th<strong>in</strong>gs are understood, transcendentally, as noth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

but simply different <strong>and</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct from (logically außer) us<br />

<strong>and</strong>, empirically, as objects that are always already<br />

subjected to those subjective conditions of time <strong>and</strong> space<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> categories (spatially außer uns).<br />

The Kantian transcendental subject is not a mere<br />

res cogitans. It is more. It comprises time <strong>and</strong> space as<br />

forms of <strong>in</strong>tuition. Kant holds this aga<strong>in</strong>st Descartes. A<br />

pure science of <strong>the</strong> res cogitans, <strong>the</strong> “I th<strong>in</strong>k”, would not<br />

get us anywhere. No rational knowledge of <strong>the</strong> outside<br />

world, even of ourselves, could be obta<strong>in</strong>ed from it. Also<br />

no limits of our empirical knowledge could be po<strong>in</strong>ted out<br />

<strong>in</strong> this way, which is someth<strong>in</strong>g important for Kant, but not<br />

for <strong>the</strong> naturalist today.<br />

Kant dist<strong>in</strong>guishes his transcendental idealism from<br />

what he calls “transcendental realism”, which is <strong>the</strong> view<br />

that time <strong>and</strong> space are th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves, <strong>in</strong>dependent<br />

of us. Common sense takes this view. If one starts <strong>in</strong> this<br />

way, one can depict oneself as some k<strong>in</strong>d of m<strong>in</strong>d-bra<strong>in</strong>body<br />

at one location <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> tree one perceives as be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

“outside”, ten meters away. Then one can start to give a<br />

causal story of sense perception, even look <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> bra<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> try to give a causal account of consciousness <strong>and</strong> our<br />

hav<strong>in</strong>g representations as well, maybe with <strong>the</strong> addition of<br />

evolutionary <strong>and</strong> social aspects. <strong>Reduction</strong>ism lives here,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Kripke <strong>and</strong> Putnam for <strong>in</strong>stance have given accounts<br />

of what we mean by “water” <strong>and</strong> H2O <strong>in</strong> this way.<br />

Transcendental realism starts with a picture of <strong>the</strong> world<br />

that is <strong>in</strong>dependent of us, with water as H2O already out<br />

<strong>the</strong>re. But if we <strong>the</strong>n place ourselves <strong>in</strong> this world, how can<br />

we be sure that this is how it really is? How can we avoid<br />

skepticism? Thus with Putnam we run <strong>in</strong>to a problem<br />

similar to Descartes’ doubt. We might be a bra<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> a vat,<br />

nay even <strong>the</strong> whole world might not exist.<br />

But accord<strong>in</strong>g to transcendental idealism, nei<strong>the</strong>r my<br />

bra<strong>in</strong>, nor <strong>the</strong> tree, nor time <strong>and</strong> space are <strong>in</strong>dependent of<br />

representational conditions. It is only as appearances that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong> time <strong>and</strong> space, <strong>and</strong> it is only as be<strong>in</strong>g subject<br />

to <strong>the</strong> categories that <strong>the</strong>y are objects. This is an <strong>in</strong>stance<br />

of <strong>the</strong> general view that any third-person account<br />

presupposes a first-person perspective. Cassam’s criticism<br />

that “Kant’s mistake was to conclude … that <strong>the</strong> unity of<br />

consciousness does not <strong>in</strong>volve be<strong>in</strong>g presented to<br />

oneself as an object at all” might still be with<strong>in</strong> this view (p.<br />

198).<br />

Experience requires an act of syn<strong>the</strong>sis, which <strong>in</strong><br />

turn requires unity. It must be my experience. For <strong>the</strong><br />

materialist it might be <strong>the</strong> bra<strong>in</strong> or <strong>the</strong> object that gives this<br />

unity. For Kant it is <strong>the</strong> act that must provide it. In<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gful perception <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> judgment we take someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

as someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> “tak<strong>in</strong>g” itself must have unity<br />

(Allison 1996, pp. 95, 102). For Kant it is transcendental<br />

consciousness (Reflexion 5661, AA 18, 318-9) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

orig<strong>in</strong>al syn<strong>the</strong>tic unity of apperception (CpR, B 134) that<br />

provide this unity, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y do this a priori, that is, prior to<br />

experience. When <strong>the</strong> materialist po<strong>in</strong>ts to <strong>the</strong> bra<strong>in</strong>, our<br />

sense organs, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir evolutionary adaptations to <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

functions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> environment, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> socio-l<strong>in</strong>guist<br />

po<strong>in</strong>ts to our language <strong>and</strong> society, Kant will po<strong>in</strong>t out that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y take time <strong>and</strong> space <strong>and</strong> empirical objects for<br />

granted, as th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby beg <strong>the</strong><br />

question. If <strong>the</strong>y also want to naturalize <strong>the</strong> act of tak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g as someth<strong>in</strong>g, we may respond with Allison that<br />

“taken <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>vestigation of its causal conditions, any<br />

token of <strong>the</strong> act of th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g is itself someth<strong>in</strong>g represented,<br />

an object for an I, which, considered as such, is not itself<br />

an object <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. In short, we return <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> end to <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>elim<strong>in</strong>ability <strong>and</strong> systematic elusiveness of this<br />

ubiquitous ‘I th<strong>in</strong>k’” (Allison, 1996, p. 104). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,<br />

we can add that <strong>the</strong> materialists will run <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> problem of<br />

skepticism, because <strong>the</strong>y cannot be sure that <strong>the</strong> objects,<br />

which for <strong>the</strong>m exist <strong>in</strong>dependently of us, are correctly<br />

represented by us whenever we have representations of<br />

<strong>the</strong>m, that is, when <strong>the</strong>y appear to us. In Kant’s words, <strong>the</strong><br />

transcendental realist <strong>the</strong>n “plays <strong>the</strong> empirical idealist” (A<br />

369).<br />

In Kant’s picture <strong>the</strong> object is noth<strong>in</strong>g but its<br />

appearance, <strong>and</strong> so <strong>the</strong> correspondence problem does not<br />

arise. Truth is <strong>in</strong> judgment, not <strong>in</strong> appearance. Ironically,<br />

one may also say that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> view of transcendental<br />

philosophy appearance already gives truth, a-le<strong>the</strong>ia, as<br />

Heidegger wanted it, <strong>in</strong>sofar as appearance <strong>and</strong> its object<br />

are not two separate th<strong>in</strong>gs (contrary to <strong>the</strong> transcendental<br />

realist’s view). The object does not need to be “deduced”<br />

from its appearance (A 372). It exists only as appearance.<br />

It is its appearance. Appearance is not someth<strong>in</strong>g extra.<br />

Imag<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g conversation between a<br />

transcendental realist (TR) <strong>and</strong> a transcendental idealist<br />

(TI):<br />

TR: “I th<strong>in</strong>k representations are generated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

bra<strong>in</strong>.”<br />

TI: “You mean processes happen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bra<strong>in</strong>?<br />

Well, <strong>the</strong>y happen <strong>in</strong> time <strong>and</strong> space. You imag<strong>in</strong>e<br />

<strong>the</strong>m as appearances.”<br />

TR: “But are <strong>the</strong>y not caused? Are not our representations,<br />

imag<strong>in</strong>ations, perceptions all caused?”<br />

391

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!