02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

of mean<strong>in</strong>g lack necessitation, logical or physical (<strong>in</strong> this<br />

respect <strong>the</strong>y are different from logical rules <strong>and</strong> physical<br />

laws) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense that we can perfectly well imag<strong>in</strong>e that<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs might have been o<strong>the</strong>rwise. This is what I call <strong>the</strong><br />

conventionality of rules, <strong>the</strong> fact that rules are arbitrary.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r merit of Kripke’s solution is that by preserv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

conventionality of rules it also preserves <strong>the</strong> descriptive<br />

aspect of rules. The way people speak is all <strong>the</strong> data we<br />

need to consider <strong>in</strong> order to know whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are rule<br />

followers. However, by putt<strong>in</strong>g emphasis on <strong>the</strong><br />

conventionality of rules, Kripke’s solution neglects <strong>the</strong><br />

normativity of rules <strong>in</strong> that it seems to suggest that <strong>the</strong> way<br />

people talk is all we need to know <strong>in</strong> order to know how<br />

<strong>the</strong>y ought to talk. Kripke’s community view suggest that<br />

we read off correctness <strong>in</strong> our follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> rules from <strong>the</strong><br />

actions of <strong>the</strong> majority. It is <strong>in</strong> this sense close to a<br />

naturalistic fallacy: <strong>the</strong> futile attempt to derive ought from<br />

is. Kripke’s suggests that agreement on what it is to follow<br />

a rule constitutes rule follow<strong>in</strong>g. I claim that this solution,<br />

like <strong>the</strong> dispositional account rejected by Kripke, cannot<br />

account for <strong>the</strong> normativity of rules.<br />

Kripke’s solution reduces rule follow<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> superrule:<br />

“act/respond as everyone else does”. Generally, he<br />

claims, <strong>the</strong>re is agreement with<strong>in</strong> a society regard<strong>in</strong>g what<br />

it is to follow a certa<strong>in</strong> rule. In this case, no one <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

society will be likely to correct it, <strong>and</strong> no one outside it has<br />

a right to correct it. This is <strong>the</strong> strength of this position but<br />

also its weakness; it does not allow for a case where<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

community agrees upon a certa<strong>in</strong> usage but is at <strong>the</strong> same<br />

time wrong <strong>in</strong> so agree<strong>in</strong>g. In <strong>the</strong> realm of ethics this<br />

situation is quite plausible; <strong>the</strong> fact that almost everyone<br />

th<strong>in</strong>ks a war is justified does not make it so. This is an<br />

ethical problem, <strong>and</strong> of course claim<strong>in</strong>g that justification<br />

depends solely on agreement <strong>in</strong> actions or op<strong>in</strong>ions would<br />

be wrong. In <strong>the</strong> realm of language <strong>the</strong> problem is not<br />

ethical but conceptual. The problem with Kripke’s solution<br />

is that it assumes that <strong>the</strong>re is a way of expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

normativity of rules merely by tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to account <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

conventional application.<br />

2. Second reduction: The reduction of rules<br />

to norms<br />

The question concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> (im)possibility of solitary rule<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g is an important test case for <strong>the</strong> community view.<br />

Kripke’s position is that if “…we th<strong>in</strong>k of Crusoe as follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

rules, we are tak<strong>in</strong>g him <strong>in</strong>to our community <strong>and</strong> apply<strong>in</strong>g<br />

our criteria for rule follow<strong>in</strong>g to him” (1982: 110). Kripke<br />

differentiates between an <strong>in</strong>dividual be<strong>in</strong>g physically isolated<br />

<strong>and</strong> his be<strong>in</strong>g considered <strong>in</strong> isolation (1982: 110). So<br />

Rob<strong>in</strong>son Crusoe, <strong>in</strong> spite of his physical isolation can be<br />

said to be a rule follower as long as he is not considered <strong>in</strong><br />

isolation. In my op<strong>in</strong>ion, <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction is an elegant vent<br />

for what could have posed a problem for <strong>the</strong> community<br />

view: on <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> community view by def<strong>in</strong>ition is<br />

<strong>in</strong>compatible with solitary rule follow<strong>in</strong>g, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, some<br />

of Crusoe’s actions <strong>in</strong>deed seem fit to be described as rule<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g activities. The dist<strong>in</strong>ction between physical <strong>and</strong><br />

epistemological isolation expla<strong>in</strong>s that <strong>the</strong> community view<br />

bans <strong>the</strong> later but not <strong>the</strong> former.<br />

Baker <strong>and</strong> Hacker, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, consider<br />

Kripke’s dist<strong>in</strong>ction ‘a muddle’ (1984: 39) that conceals <strong>the</strong><br />

real question at h<strong>and</strong>: had, or had not Crusoe been<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g rules? The dist<strong>in</strong>ction blurs out <strong>the</strong> fact that both<br />

<strong>the</strong> physically isolated person <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> one considered <strong>in</strong><br />

isolation can manifest a rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g behavior. The fact<br />

that this is so, <strong>the</strong>y claim, is shown by Crusoe’s regulative<br />

practice; he uses <strong>the</strong> rule as “a canon or norm of<br />

284<br />

Two <strong>Reduction</strong>s of ‘rule’ — Dana Riesenfeld<br />

correctness” (1984: 39) <strong>and</strong> is able to correct his own<br />

mistakes when <strong>and</strong> if <strong>the</strong>y occur. Thus rule follow<strong>in</strong>g for<br />

Baker <strong>and</strong> Hacker is perform<strong>in</strong>g an activity which is regular<br />

<strong>and</strong> which can be corrected by <strong>the</strong> rule follower. To <strong>the</strong>m,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> question whe<strong>the</strong>r anyone else observ<strong>in</strong>g or<br />

consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> isolated <strong>in</strong>dividual can or cannot detect <strong>the</strong><br />

rule follow<strong>in</strong>g behavior is dist<strong>in</strong>ct from <strong>the</strong> question<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual has <strong>in</strong> fact been<br />

Baker <strong>and</strong> Hacker’s critique of Kripke is<br />

encapsulated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir different <strong>in</strong>terpretation of <strong>the</strong> term<br />

‘private’. While Kripke <strong>in</strong>terprets ‘private’ as <strong>the</strong> opposite of<br />

‘social’ (hence <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between physical solitude<br />

<strong>and</strong> epistemic solitude <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> prima facie impossibility of<br />

solitary rule follow<strong>in</strong>g), for Baker <strong>and</strong> Hacker ‘private’<br />

means <strong>the</strong> opposite of ‘public’. Consequently, rulefollow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

is essentially public <strong>in</strong> nature but not necessarily<br />

social (see also 1985: 161-165). That is why <strong>the</strong> question<br />

of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> outside observer may or may not detect <strong>the</strong><br />

rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g tak<strong>in</strong>g place, will f<strong>in</strong>d it hard (perhaps even<br />

impossible!) or easy to learn <strong>the</strong> rules he is observ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

becomes secondary. What is crucial is that <strong>the</strong> practice is<br />

essentially public. Baker <strong>and</strong> Hacker, <strong>the</strong>n, defend a<br />

position opt<strong>in</strong>g for solitary-public rule follow<strong>in</strong>g. 3 Follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

rules, <strong>the</strong>y emphasize, “…is not a matter of collective<br />

dispositions, but of a normative practice, which may be<br />

collective, but need not be” (1984: 74). Kripke, <strong>the</strong>y claim,<br />

is deriv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> answer to <strong>the</strong> normative question ‘how<br />

ought we to follow rules?’ from <strong>the</strong> empirical question ‘how<br />

do most people follow rules?’ because ‘rule’ is a normative<br />

concept, it cannot be claimed that <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g of rules<br />

can be <strong>the</strong> object of observation. It is impossible to derive<br />

<strong>the</strong> norms of a given society by look<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> society’s<br />

conduct. Without stipulation of a rule, actions are but<br />

‘empty vehicles’ of what would have been considered a<br />

norm, had we a rule. By consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> rule as dist<strong>in</strong>ct<br />

from its application Kripke’s analysis not only ignores <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>ternal relation between <strong>the</strong> rule <strong>and</strong> its application, but<br />

also creates a situation where<strong>in</strong> agreement becomes an<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternal property of <strong>the</strong> rule. This is nonsense, Baker <strong>and</strong><br />

Hacker claim, for <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> test of <strong>the</strong> rule’s correct<br />

application becomes correspondence with community<br />

agreement, <strong>the</strong> action of <strong>the</strong> majority.<br />

However, this position, I argue, is highly problematic<br />

by <strong>the</strong>ir own assumptions. The alternative position<br />

presented by Baker <strong>and</strong> Hacker, I claim, only succeeds <strong>in</strong><br />

solv<strong>in</strong>g those problems by creat<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>rs, no less<br />

resound<strong>in</strong>g, namely that of reduc<strong>in</strong>g rules to norms. Such<br />

reduction, i.e., a normative explanation of rule is at <strong>the</strong><br />

same time devoid of conventionality, of <strong>the</strong> capacity to<br />

describe how <strong>in</strong> fact a l<strong>in</strong>guistic community follows its<br />

rules. Although follow<strong>in</strong>g rules is a practice, it is wrong,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y say, to th<strong>in</strong>k of it as essentially a social practice<br />

(1985:164). Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s conception of practice dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

it to be shareable, not shared. For a practice to be<br />

considered rule follow<strong>in</strong>g “it must be possible to teach a<br />

technique of apply<strong>in</strong>g rules to o<strong>the</strong>rs, by grasp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

criteria of correctness, to determ<strong>in</strong>e whe<strong>the</strong>r a given act is<br />

a correct application of <strong>the</strong> rule” (ibid). Baker <strong>and</strong> Hacker<br />

characterize <strong>the</strong> practice of rule follow<strong>in</strong>g as essentially<br />

possible but not as essentially occurr<strong>in</strong>g, a rule follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

practice which is possibly learnable, teachable correctable<br />

<strong>and</strong> regular. None of <strong>the</strong>se conditions are sufficient by<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves. But a rule follow<strong>in</strong>g practice is one which,<br />

when meet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se conditions, could possibly occur.<br />

Baker <strong>and</strong> Hacker characterize a rule follow<strong>in</strong>g practice as<br />

3 Baker <strong>and</strong> Hacker claim that this is Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s position <strong>in</strong> unpublished<br />

manuscripts (see, e.g., 1985: 172).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!