02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

imperatives, or comm<strong>and</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form of admonish<strong>in</strong>g<br />

adherence to rules that we assent to follow. The <strong>in</strong>tuitionist<br />

Dummett, whose position Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s resembles, refers<br />

to ma<strong>the</strong>matical statements as quasi-assertions:<br />

Quasi-assertions are declarative sentences which<br />

are not associated with determ<strong>in</strong>ate conditions of<br />

truth <strong>and</strong> falsity but share with assertions properly<br />

so-called <strong>the</strong> feature that <strong>the</strong>re is such a th<strong>in</strong>g as<br />

assent<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>m; where such assent is<br />

communally understood as a commitment to some<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite type of l<strong>in</strong>guistic or non-l<strong>in</strong>guistic conduct,<br />

<strong>and</strong> receives explicit expression precisely by <strong>the</strong><br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> quasi-assertion. 13<br />

The subtle aspect of underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matical statements as <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple verifiable aga<strong>in</strong>st<br />

an objective reality, versus hav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> character of be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

ratified by voluntarily acceptance, is that although we seek<br />

to preserve some sense of non-arbitrary structure, we<br />

must locate its apparent “necessity” <strong>in</strong> our discretionary<br />

compliance ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>in</strong> some facet of extra-mental<br />

reality. This necessity has <strong>the</strong> form of will<strong>in</strong>gly b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

ourselves to a normative correctness that we enact <strong>in</strong> our<br />

practice. Hence we have <strong>the</strong> sufficient leverage to not only<br />

ask “[o]f someone who is tra<strong>in</strong>ed [<strong>in</strong> a specific type of rulefollow<strong>in</strong>g]<br />

‘How will he <strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> rule <strong>in</strong> this case?’”, but<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r to raise <strong>the</strong> question, “How ought he to <strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong><br />

rule for this case”? 14<br />

This view of ma<strong>the</strong>matics as hav<strong>in</strong>g a humanly<br />

devised comm<strong>and</strong> structure <strong>in</strong>stead of a structure <strong>in</strong>sured<br />

by objective reality alters our picture of <strong>the</strong> type of<br />

normative guidance underly<strong>in</strong>g ma<strong>the</strong>matical judgment.<br />

Instead of be<strong>in</strong>g guided <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g ma<strong>the</strong>matical<br />

statements by facts, we consider that “all ma<strong>the</strong>matical<br />

propositions [are] expressed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> imperative, e.g., ‘Let 10<br />

x 10 be 100.’” 15 The significance is that this depiction of<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matics makes <strong>the</strong> consistency of its structure<br />

dependent on our voluntary commitment to uphold<br />

conceptual relations <strong>in</strong> specific ways:<br />

Such an account is exactly what we should<br />

<strong>in</strong>tuitively propose for sentences express<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g of a promise. No one would ord<strong>in</strong>arily<br />

suppose that <strong>the</strong> use of sentences of <strong>the</strong> form, ‘I<br />

promise to …’ is best understood as <strong>the</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g of a<br />

statement, true or false; though <strong>the</strong>ir be<strong>in</strong>g prefixed<br />

by ‘it is true that …’ is grammatical sense. 16<br />

The promissory quality, <strong>the</strong>n, of ma<strong>the</strong>matical normativity<br />

is that ma<strong>the</strong>matical rules suggest what we “ought to<br />

conclude,” <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> participat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

exercises we accede to draw <strong>the</strong> conclusion implied by <strong>the</strong><br />

rule. It is not that some feature of an objective world of<br />

numbers <strong>in</strong>tercedes to form <strong>the</strong> basis of our judgment <strong>in</strong> a<br />

necessary fashion. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

we agree to abide by <strong>the</strong> rules as prefigur<strong>in</strong>g or<br />

comm<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g our judgment. If we consider <strong>the</strong> role proofs<br />

play <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics, “it marks not a discovery of certa<strong>in</strong><br />

objective liaisons between concepts, but someth<strong>in</strong>g more<br />

like a resolution on our part so to <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

future.” 17<br />

13 Wright, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, 155.<br />

14 Ludwig Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, Remarks on <strong>the</strong> Foundations of Ma<strong>the</strong>matics, ed. by<br />

G.H. von Wright, R. Rhees, <strong>and</strong> G.E.M. Anscombe, trans. By G.E.M. Anscombe<br />

(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996) (RFM), V-9, p. 267.<br />

15 Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, RFM, 155.<br />

15 Ludwig Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, RFM, V-17, p. 276.<br />

16 Wright, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, 157.<br />

17 Wright, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, 135.<br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> on Count<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Political Economy — Sonja M. Amadae<br />

If our underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> normativity structur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

apparently necessary truths <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics rests on our<br />

commitment to follow <strong>the</strong> rules of ma<strong>the</strong>matics, <strong>the</strong>n it is<br />

possible to see that <strong>the</strong> rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g nature of math is<br />

little different from o<strong>the</strong>r rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutions<br />

throughout our society. This opens <strong>the</strong> possibility of<br />

consider<strong>in</strong>g that social-norms that st<strong>and</strong> as a system of<br />

rules have as much sanctity as do <strong>the</strong> rules of<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matics. Typically, social norms are regarded as<br />

subject to preference; ei<strong>the</strong>r an <strong>in</strong>dividual prefers to follow<br />

a social norm or not; if she chooses to follow a social<br />

norm, this is because she prefers to do so. However, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

case of ma<strong>the</strong>matical judgment, preference is seldom<br />

<strong>in</strong>voked as a source of decision over <strong>the</strong> result of a<br />

calculation or proof.<br />

This recast<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> foundation, as it were, of<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matics from fact <strong>and</strong> objective truth to socially<br />

constructed <strong>and</strong> ratified laws suggests <strong>the</strong> possibility for<br />

draw<strong>in</strong>g a parallel between legal systems of rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>and</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical systems. In his essay, “The Groundless<br />

Normativity of Instrumental Rationality,” Donald Hub<strong>in</strong><br />

argues that neo-Humean <strong>in</strong>strumentalists “must engage <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> same ‘lower<strong>in</strong>g of expectations’ [of <strong>the</strong> source of<br />

normativity of <strong>in</strong>strumental rationality to <strong>the</strong> same level]<br />

that <strong>the</strong> legal positivist must.” 18 For Hub<strong>in</strong>, practical<br />

rationality, of which <strong>in</strong>strumentality is part, is not an<br />

objective matter. In mak<strong>in</strong>g his po<strong>in</strong>t, he draws on legal<br />

positivism’s retreat from natural law <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>and</strong> draws on<br />

H.L.A. Hart to exp<strong>and</strong> on this view. 19 Hub<strong>in</strong> is mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

po<strong>in</strong>t that even though a legal system provides a<br />

normative basis for action, it cannot ground its ultimate<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. I am rework<strong>in</strong>g Hub<strong>in</strong>’s parallel between<br />

positive law <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>strumental reason to contrast a realist<br />

account of math with an alternative declarative<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g. In an anti-realist ma<strong>the</strong>matics, <strong>the</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g<br />

quality of rules only holds <strong>in</strong>sofar as we assent to <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

It has traditionally been <strong>the</strong> case <strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong><br />

political normativity has been viewed as of a lesser<br />

pedigree than <strong>in</strong>strumental <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical normativity<br />

<strong>in</strong>sofar as <strong>the</strong> former is conditional, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter is nonnegotiable.<br />

For example, Phillip Pettit provides an<br />

explanation for how social norms may be derived from<br />

<strong>in</strong>strumental agency as <strong>the</strong> former is conditional on<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual rational self <strong>in</strong>terest. 20 In his Theory of Justice,<br />

John Rawls was widely criticized from with<strong>in</strong> rational<br />

choice <strong>the</strong>ory for plac<strong>in</strong>g action accord<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> “<strong>the</strong><br />

reasonable,” which <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>the</strong> political <strong>the</strong>oretic concept<br />

of fair play, on par with agency conform<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> dictates<br />

of expected utility <strong>the</strong>ory. 21 It was not automatically<br />

obvious from with<strong>in</strong> rational choice <strong>the</strong>ory that agents had<br />

a duty to uphold <strong>the</strong> rules of government if <strong>the</strong>y did not<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r an agent’s ends <strong>in</strong> each <strong>and</strong> every circumstance of<br />

action. 22 Therefore, without some sanction<strong>in</strong>g device that<br />

alters payoffs, <strong>the</strong> rule of law does not <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> of itself<br />

provide a reason for action that trumps agents’<br />

preferences over end states. Rawls concludes of his<br />

contrast<strong>in</strong>g approach to justice as fairness, “There is no<br />

thought of try<strong>in</strong>g to derive <strong>the</strong> content of justice with<strong>in</strong> a<br />

18 Donald Hub<strong>in</strong>, "The Groundless Normativity of Instrumental Rationality",<br />

The Journal of <strong>Philosophy</strong> 98:9(2001), 445-468, 466.<br />

19 Hub<strong>in</strong>, “Groundless Normativity,” 463.<br />

20 Philip Pettit, “Virtus normativa: Rational Choice Perspectives,” <strong>in</strong> his Rules,<br />

Reasons, <strong>and</strong> Norms (Oxford University Press, 2002), 308-343.<br />

21 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Harvard University Press, 1971); John<br />

Rawls, “Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical,” <strong>Philosophy</strong> <strong>and</strong> Public<br />

Affairs, 14:3 (summer, 1985), 223-51.<br />

22 This is <strong>the</strong> problem David Gauthier faces <strong>in</strong> Morals by Agreement (Oxford<br />

University Press, 1985).<br />

15

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!