02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

assumptions. Loewer argues that notion of <strong>the</strong> natural law<br />

<strong>in</strong> scientific practice does not require <strong>the</strong> governist idea<br />

that laws have to govern events so it is right to ab<strong>and</strong>on<br />

governism. However, Balashov (2002) as a non-humean<br />

can also appeal to scientific practice <strong>in</strong> order to show that<br />

humean solutions are untenable. He argues that laws can<br />

be strongly supported by empirical evidence <strong>and</strong> have<br />

explanatory power only if <strong>the</strong>y are necessary. It is clear<br />

that what Balashov has <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d is <strong>the</strong> concept of m<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>dependent<br />

natural laws which can be discovered with <strong>the</strong><br />

help of our science.<br />

I th<strong>in</strong>k that without a sharp dist<strong>in</strong>ction between notions<br />

of natural laws <strong>and</strong> scientific laws, it is impossible to<br />

see <strong>the</strong> problem as clearly as we need. The concept of<br />

natural laws <strong>in</strong>volves universality, so “laws of nature without<br />

universality” is a contradiction while <strong>the</strong>re is no such a<br />

contradiction <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sentence that “<strong>the</strong> laws of <strong>the</strong>rmal expansion<br />

is not universal”. This can be demonstrated easily:<br />

if ΔL = k.L0 .ΔT were an universal truth it should be impossible<br />

to cite situations where <strong>the</strong> relation between L0, ΔT<br />

<strong>and</strong> ΔL falls, but <strong>the</strong>re is an <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite number of provisos<br />

implicit <strong>in</strong> a statement like “without hammer<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> heated<br />

iron rod <strong>in</strong>ward at one end ...”, so it is impossible to state a<br />

genu<strong>in</strong>e law-statement. Thus scientific laws cannot be<br />

universal, while implicit <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept of natural laws we<br />

presuppose universality. scientific laws – at least most of<br />

<strong>the</strong>m – certa<strong>in</strong>ly fail to be<strong>in</strong>g equal to natural laws.<br />

A metaphysically moderate version of<br />

Humean Supervenience<br />

I am agnostic about <strong>the</strong> feasibility of metaphysical approaches<br />

so I will focus on <strong>the</strong> question of scientific laws<br />

<strong>in</strong>stead. As I said scientific laws – or at least lots of <strong>the</strong>m –<br />

fail to be universal. What more can we say about scientific<br />

laws? Earman <strong>and</strong> Roberts (2005) identify laws with<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matical treatments of certa<strong>in</strong> problems. They wrote:<br />

“In modern physics (by which we mean, at least, physics<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce Newton), <strong>the</strong> typical form of a problem is that of solv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

a differential equation (or a system of such equations)<br />

subject to certa<strong>in</strong> boundary conditions, which typically<br />

<strong>in</strong>clude <strong>in</strong>itial conditions.” (Earman & Roberts 2005, 13).<br />

The difference between nomic <strong>and</strong> non-nomic facts is<br />

merely a methodological one. We have to dist<strong>in</strong>guish<br />

boundary <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial conditions <strong>and</strong> equations while we try<br />

to solve a problem, but this difference is not ontological.<br />

This def<strong>in</strong>ition restricts <strong>the</strong> field of scientific laws to laws<br />

which can be formulated ma<strong>the</strong>matically. Thus if we hold<br />

this view as an appropriate account of scientific laws, we<br />

cannot count many of scientific generalizations as laws;<br />

e.g. laws of biology will be non-laws accord<strong>in</strong>g to this<br />

analysis. I do not th<strong>in</strong>k that this would be <strong>the</strong> right move.<br />

However, implicit <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> view presented by Earman <strong>and</strong><br />

Roberts (2005) <strong>the</strong>re is someth<strong>in</strong>g resembl<strong>in</strong>g to Hume's<br />

orig<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>sight, that nomic relations among events is not<br />

observable. They def<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> Humean base as follows: “The<br />

Humean base at a given world is <strong>the</strong> set of non-nomic<br />

facts at that world that can be <strong>the</strong> output of a reliable, spatiotemporally<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ite observation or measurment procedure.”<br />

(Earman & Roberts 2005,17).<br />

182<br />

A Metaphysically Moderate Version of Humean Supervenience — Szilárd Koczka<br />

Earman <strong>and</strong> Roberts suggest a modal<br />

characterization of HB. In <strong>the</strong> light of <strong>the</strong>ir analysis a fact<br />

belongs to <strong>the</strong> HB if <strong>and</strong> only if <strong>the</strong>re is a nomologically<br />

possible observaiton or measurement procedure to detect<br />

it. The explanation will be circular only if we <strong>in</strong>terpret<br />

nomological possibility as a m<strong>in</strong>d-<strong>and</strong>-<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong>dependent<br />

feature of our world. I prefer <strong>the</strong> alternative – ontologically<br />

less committed – <strong>in</strong>terpretation that someth<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

nomologically possible if it is compatible with our scientific<br />

laws. It is an epistemological characterization of<br />

nomological possibility <strong>and</strong> it has its own problems, but I<br />

th<strong>in</strong>k this is <strong>the</strong> best we can offer. There is a bit obscure<br />

notion with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ition presented by Earman <strong>and</strong><br />

Roberts, namely reliability. To disperse this obscurity I<br />

def<strong>in</strong>e reliability as follows: An observation or<br />

measurement procedure can be reliable, if it is consistent<br />

with our already accepted <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>and</strong> all observable fact.<br />

In addition, reliability has a normative feature: what is <strong>and</strong><br />

what is not reliable depends on our current <strong>the</strong>ories. This<br />

normative feature can be understood with <strong>the</strong> help of<br />

Kuhn's (1996) term<strong>in</strong>ology. Even if it is <strong>in</strong>correct to talk<br />

about “Scientific revolution”, <strong>the</strong> core idea that scientific<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ards can change with paradigms seems plausible<br />

enough. Thus I ref<strong>in</strong>e my def<strong>in</strong>ition: A measurement<br />

process is reliable, if it is consistent with our already<br />

accepted <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>and</strong> directly observed facts, <strong>and</strong> it fits to<br />

our current scientific st<strong>and</strong>ards.<br />

A moderate version of Humean supervenience as a<br />

m<strong>in</strong>imalist <strong>the</strong>ory states that we can develop predictable<br />

useful scientific laws as <strong>in</strong>ference rules that belongs to<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> models or systems. The models we develop are<br />

useful <strong>in</strong>struments of explanation <strong>and</strong> prediction, but we<br />

can never be <strong>in</strong> an epistemological position that enables<br />

us to declare that <strong>in</strong> scientific research we can discover <strong>the</strong><br />

m<strong>in</strong>d-<strong>and</strong>-<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong>dependent natural laws. We have an<br />

ability to perceive relevant patterns of non-nomic facts,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re by creat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>strumentally useful models or systems,<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> very natural laws. The Humean Base<br />

consists of facts that we can acquire directly or with <strong>the</strong><br />

help of any reliable observational or measurement<br />

procedure. One can argue, that <strong>the</strong> moderate version of<br />

HS is not <strong>the</strong> same as that of Lewis elaborated, <strong>and</strong> it is<br />

obviously true. Why call this <strong>the</strong>sis Humean<br />

Supervenience after all? Lewis dedicated his <strong>the</strong>sis as “<strong>in</strong><br />

honor of <strong>the</strong> greater denier of necessary connection”(Lewis<br />

1986,ix), however it is possible to come up with a<br />

supervenience <strong>the</strong>sis about laws which can express<br />

Hume's orig<strong>in</strong>al – epistemological – motivations about<br />

nomic relations.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!