02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Exorciz<strong>in</strong>g Gettier<br />

Claudio F. Costa, Natal, Brazil<br />

50<br />

Knowledge is not simply justified true belief,<br />

but it is justified true belief, justifiably arrived at.<br />

Robert J. Fogel<strong>in</strong><br />

Gettier’s problem 1 seems to be a daunt<strong>in</strong>g treat to our<br />

belief <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> rationality of <strong>the</strong> human knowledge. In what<br />

follows I <strong>in</strong>tend to show with some formal precision <strong>the</strong><br />

natural way out of <strong>the</strong> trap.<br />

Us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> symbol a to a person, K to knowledge, B<br />

to <strong>the</strong> belief, E to a reasonable justify<strong>in</strong>g evidence (justification),<br />

<strong>and</strong> p to <strong>the</strong> proposition, we might symbolize <strong>the</strong><br />

tripartite def<strong>in</strong>ition of knowledge as follows:<br />

(i) (ii) (iii)<br />

(Df.1) aKp = p & aBp & aEBp<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to this def<strong>in</strong>ition, a knows that p (aKp) means<br />

<strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> conjunction of <strong>the</strong>se three conditions,<br />

namely (i) that p is true, (ii) that a believes that p is true,<br />

<strong>and</strong> (iii) that a has a reasonable justification for her belief<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> truth of p. As it is well-known, Gettier’s problem<br />

arises from <strong>the</strong> discovery of counterexamples to this def<strong>in</strong>ition,<br />

namely, from cases where <strong>the</strong> person a fails to atta<strong>in</strong><br />

knowledge though satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se three conditions.<br />

To remember Gettier’s counterexamples, consider<br />

<strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g 2 . Suppose that professor Stone said to Mary<br />

yesterday that he would come to <strong>the</strong> university this night to<br />

give a lecture. S<strong>in</strong>ce Mary knows that Stone is a highly<br />

responsible person, she can claim that she knows that he<br />

came to <strong>the</strong> university this night. However, unknown to<br />

her, one of Stone’s sons suffered an accident <strong>and</strong> he<br />

needed to drop <strong>the</strong> lecture. However, it is true that he<br />

came to <strong>the</strong> university, s<strong>in</strong>ce he was momentarily <strong>in</strong> his<br />

room to take some documents. Mary’s claim to know that<br />

Stone came to <strong>the</strong> University this night seems to satisfy<br />

<strong>the</strong> conditions to <strong>the</strong> traditional def<strong>in</strong>ition: it is a true belief<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> justification presented by her is reasonable<br />

enough. Never<strong>the</strong>less, its truth is only accidentally<br />

achieved <strong>and</strong> nobody would say that Mary really knows<br />

that Stone was at <strong>the</strong> university tonight.<br />

As it was sometimes noted, <strong>the</strong>re is a<br />

straightforward <strong>and</strong> effective way to answer <strong>the</strong> problem,<br />

which seems to be nearly buried under <strong>the</strong> considerable<br />

amount of alternative answers explored <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature 3 . It<br />

consists simply <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> request that a sound epistemic<br />

justification must belong to what we are able to accept as<br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> proposition p true 4 . So, Mary’s justification for<br />

1 E. L. Gettier: “Is Justified Belief Knowledge?” Analysis 23, 6, 1963, 121-23.<br />

2 I take this example (with slight changes) from D. J. O’Connor <strong>and</strong> Brian Carr,<br />

Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Theory of Knowledge (The Harverster Press: Brighton<br />

1982).<br />

3 Similar considerations can be found <strong>in</strong> D. J. O’Connor <strong>and</strong> B. Carr, Introduction<br />

to <strong>the</strong> Theory of Knowledge, p. 82. The orig<strong>in</strong> of this view seems to be due<br />

to Robert F. Almeder, particularly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> paper “Truth <strong>and</strong> Evidence”, The<br />

Philosophical Quarterly 24, 1974, 365-68. The most orig<strong>in</strong>al <strong>and</strong> compell<strong>in</strong>g<br />

defense of a similar view can be found <strong>in</strong> Robert Fogel<strong>in</strong>’s book, Pyrrhonian<br />

Reflections on Knowledge <strong>and</strong> Justification (Oxford University Press: Oxford<br />

1994), chapter 1.<br />

4 This requirement was stated by D. J. O’Connor <strong>and</strong> by Brian Carr, who also<br />

say that “<strong>the</strong> reason why <strong>the</strong> proposition is true must not be <strong>in</strong>dependent on<br />

<strong>the</strong> facts asserted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition constitut<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> grounds for <strong>the</strong> belief”,<br />

claim<strong>in</strong>g for elaboration (Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Theory of Knowledge, p. 81).<br />

Robert Fogel<strong>in</strong> stated <strong>the</strong> same po<strong>in</strong>t more concisely his def<strong>in</strong>ition of knowledge:<br />

“S knows that P iff S justifiably came to believe that P on grounds that<br />

establish <strong>the</strong> truth of P” (Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge <strong>and</strong> Justification,<br />

p. 28)<br />

her belief that professor Stone came to <strong>the</strong> University this<br />

night, based on <strong>the</strong> evidence given by his statement that<br />

he would give a lecture, might be reasonable, but is<br />

epistemically unsound, s<strong>in</strong>ce this <strong>in</strong>formation is no part of<br />

what we – as <strong>the</strong> epistemic evaluators of Mary’s<br />

knowledge claim – are prepared to accept as mak<strong>in</strong>g true<br />

<strong>the</strong> belief that Stone came to <strong>the</strong> university this night.<br />

Reasonability is not enough. A justification must also be<br />

epistemically sound, by mak<strong>in</strong>g itself acceptable to <strong>the</strong><br />

epistemic evaluators of a knowledge claimer a as mak<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

proposition p true 5 . In <strong>the</strong> case of <strong>the</strong> gettierian<br />

counterexamples, <strong>the</strong>se epistemic evaluators have always<br />

some <strong>in</strong>formation that overrides <strong>the</strong> epistemic soundness<br />

of <strong>the</strong> reasonable justification given by <strong>the</strong> knowledge<br />

claimer. 6<br />

My aim here is to improve <strong>the</strong> tripartite def<strong>in</strong>ition of<br />

knowledge by stat<strong>in</strong>g more formaly this <strong>in</strong>tuitive solution.<br />

This can be done by mak<strong>in</strong>g explicit <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal l<strong>in</strong>k<br />

between <strong>the</strong> condition of justification <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> condition of<br />

truth. In order to do it, we shall review <strong>the</strong> formulation of<br />

<strong>the</strong> conditions (i) <strong>and</strong> (iii) of (Df.1).<br />

We beg<strong>in</strong> with <strong>the</strong> condition of truth. As it appears <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> traditional def<strong>in</strong>ition, it is surely a simplification. For it<br />

seems like <strong>the</strong> truth-value of <strong>the</strong> proposition when it is<br />

contemplated by God. S<strong>in</strong>ce God doesn’t need to verify<br />

anyth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> order to know <strong>the</strong> truth, he does not need to<br />

consider whe<strong>the</strong>r any truth-condition is satisfied. So, for<br />

him “p” or “p is true” is enough. However, if we <strong>in</strong>tend to<br />

make justice to <strong>the</strong> condition of <strong>the</strong> truth of p as it is known<br />

by us (that is, by <strong>the</strong> knowledge-evaluators of knowledgeclaimers),<br />

we need to consider whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> truthconditions<br />

were satisfied. Now, how to do it? We need first<br />

to see that, when an evidence E for <strong>the</strong> ascent of p is<br />

found, it must be seen by us as sufficient to make <strong>the</strong><br />

proposition p true. The mean<strong>in</strong>g of ‘sufficient’ here can be<br />

made precise as follows:<br />

An evidence E is sufficient for <strong>the</strong> assent of p as<br />

true iff E makes p ei<strong>the</strong>r (i) necessarily true (when p<br />

is a non-empirical, deductively grounded truth) or (ii)<br />

probable <strong>in</strong> a very high level (for <strong>the</strong> cases of empirical,<br />

<strong>in</strong>ductively grounded truths) 7 .<br />

We can <strong>in</strong>troduce <strong>the</strong> symbol ‘~>’ (to be read as “is sufficient<br />

to”) <strong>in</strong> order to express this conditional. Thus, given<br />

<strong>the</strong> evidence E for <strong>the</strong> ascent of p, this means that E ~> p,<br />

<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, that for us ei<strong>the</strong>r E makes p necessarily<br />

true or very probably true.<br />

With this <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d we can <strong>in</strong>troduce <strong>the</strong> symbol E* to<br />

designate <strong>the</strong> set of all justify<strong>in</strong>g evidences that we<br />

consider <strong>in</strong>dividually sufficient for <strong>the</strong> truth or falsity of p <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> already specified sense. To give an example: suppose<br />

5 My dist<strong>in</strong>ction between a reasonable justification <strong>and</strong> an epistemically sound<br />

justification is equivalent to <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between a personal justification<br />

(epistemically responsible) <strong>and</strong> a justification given on <strong>the</strong> basis of adequate<br />

grounds. See Michael Williams, Problems of Knowledge: a Critical Introduction<br />

to <strong>Philosophy</strong> (Oxford University Press: Oxford 2001) pp. 22-23.<br />

6 The words ‘we’ <strong>and</strong> ‘us’ po<strong>in</strong>t usually to <strong>the</strong> knowledge-evaluators, with <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

usually wider <strong>in</strong>formational set. However, this does not precludes <strong>the</strong> possibility<br />

that <strong>the</strong> knowledge-evaluator is <strong>the</strong> knowledge-claimer herself, by mak<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

self-evaluation of her own past knowledge claims.<br />

7 I am not consider<strong>in</strong>g Kripkian cases like that of necessary a posteriori beliefs<br />

derived from E (<strong>the</strong>y are also controversial).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!