02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Ontological Naturalism<br />

Marc<strong>in</strong> Miłkowski, Warsaw, Pol<strong>and</strong><br />

In most discussions, “naturalism” is thought to be<br />

equivalent to “physicalism”. For example, David<br />

Pap<strong>in</strong>eau’s book (Pap<strong>in</strong>eau 1993) doesn’t even mention<br />

<strong>the</strong> word “naturalism,” <strong>and</strong> uses “physicalism” <strong>in</strong>stead. The<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard text-book def<strong>in</strong>itions follow <strong>the</strong> same pattern<br />

(Schmitt 1995; Guttenplan 1994).<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, it could seem that <strong>the</strong> term<br />

“ontological naturalism” is simply reducible to “physicalism”<br />

<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>refore, can be elim<strong>in</strong>ated from <strong>the</strong> philosophical<br />

vocabulary. I will argue that naturalism is not to be reduced<br />

to physicalism, <strong>and</strong> that both positions should be<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guished. Physicalism must be committed to <strong>the</strong> view<br />

that all objects are physical, <strong>and</strong> that implies that objects<br />

mentioned <strong>in</strong> special sciences, for example, are reducible<br />

to physical. Naturalism doesn’t have to embrace this view.<br />

This is not to say that naturalism is necessarily antireductive;<br />

on <strong>the</strong> contrary, it has to imply that all objects<br />

are natural objects, <strong>and</strong> that means that <strong>the</strong>y are reducible<br />

to natural objects. The ma<strong>in</strong> difference is that narrow<br />

physicalism implies unity of science, <strong>and</strong> naturalism can<br />

rema<strong>in</strong> neutral towards it, nei<strong>the</strong>r deny<strong>in</strong>g nor accept<strong>in</strong>g it.<br />

To wit, naturalism is a broader notion <strong>and</strong> covers various<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r positions such as broad <strong>and</strong> narrow physicalism.<br />

Physicalism is usually def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> two basic ways: (1)<br />

via <strong>the</strong> notion of a physical object; (2) via <strong>the</strong> notion of a<br />

physical <strong>the</strong>ory (Stoljar 2001). What is notable is that it’s<br />

impossible to def<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> notion of a physical object without<br />

imply<strong>in</strong>g a <strong>the</strong>ory of it (it’s not observational), <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, any physical <strong>the</strong>ory will imply a notion of a<br />

physical object. So, both ways are <strong>in</strong>extricably l<strong>in</strong>ked to<br />

one ano<strong>the</strong>r but <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory-based approach has two<br />

advantages: first, its ontological commitments can be<br />

analyzed <strong>the</strong> same way <strong>the</strong>y are analyzed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of<br />

scientific <strong>the</strong>ories; second, it will clearly present <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical background.<br />

Even if <strong>the</strong> notion of a physical object is def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> a<br />

fashion that is deliberately non-scientific (see Strawson<br />

2006), it will imply a <strong>the</strong>ory at least <strong>in</strong> a sense that <strong>the</strong><br />

notion of <strong>the</strong> physical cannot be taken to be purely<br />

observational. If this <strong>the</strong>ory is based on a priori<br />

assumptions that are outright <strong>in</strong>compatible with <strong>the</strong> physics<br />

as we know it, it should be dismissed as highly<br />

objectionable example of armchair <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g. In o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

words, object-based def<strong>in</strong>ition of physicalism must be<br />

v<strong>in</strong>dicated aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> objection that it is arbitrary <strong>and</strong><br />

unjustified. Even if <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ition is supposed to be based<br />

on conceptual analysis that starts with an <strong>in</strong>tuitive notion of<br />

<strong>the</strong> physical (as <strong>in</strong> Strawson 2006), it should be asked<br />

which concepts were analyzed to reach this def<strong>in</strong>ition. If<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are natural language concepts, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

guarantee <strong>the</strong>y are correct: we still speak of <strong>the</strong> Sun ris<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

If <strong>the</strong>y are scientific concepts, like <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case when <strong>the</strong><br />

physical object is def<strong>in</strong>ed as whatever exists <strong>in</strong> timespace,<br />

it is already <strong>the</strong>ory-laden. Ei<strong>the</strong>r way, <strong>the</strong> object-based<br />

approach collapses <strong>in</strong>to an implicit version of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orybased<br />

physicalism.<br />

Theory-based physicalism is not trouble-free,<br />

however. It cannot offer clear-cut conceptual solutions, if<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory it appeals to is scientific. For example, it is hard<br />

to stay nom<strong>in</strong>alist while posit<strong>in</strong>g ideally black bodies or<br />

timespace po<strong>in</strong>ts. Moreover, physical <strong>the</strong>ories of <strong>the</strong><br />

genesis of timespace can hypo<strong>the</strong>size that <strong>the</strong>re were<br />

once non-timespace objects that gave rise to timespace. A<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory-based physicalist will have to embrace <strong>the</strong> claim (if<br />

scientifically valid), even if it would seem counter<strong>in</strong>tuitive to<br />

her.<br />

This is a m<strong>in</strong>or problem compared to an objection<br />

that if <strong>the</strong>ory-based physicalism refers to scientific physics,<br />

it is false <strong>in</strong>sofar as current physics is not complete,<br />

abounds <strong>in</strong> tensions between disparate <strong>the</strong>ories (e.g.,<br />

quantum mechanics <strong>and</strong> relativity <strong>the</strong>ory) <strong>and</strong> has obvious<br />

gaps. In reply, most physicalists claim that <strong>the</strong>y refer to an<br />

ideal physics. Yet, <strong>the</strong>y don’t care to explicate <strong>the</strong> notion of<br />

ideal physics. Carl Hempel formulated a dilemma:<br />

physicalism is def<strong>in</strong>ed ei<strong>the</strong>r with current physics, which is<br />

almost surely false, or with ideal physics, which is<br />

unknown, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore cannot be rationally asserted<br />

(Hempel 1970). Object-based physicalism, as it implies a<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory, has to face it as well.<br />

There are two strategies for deal<strong>in</strong>g with this<br />

dilemma. First is to def<strong>in</strong>e ideal physics <strong>in</strong> terms of<br />

empirical accessibility (Guttenplan 1994), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> second<br />

is to specify requirements that ideal physics will have to<br />

meet. The first strategy implies ei<strong>the</strong>r that physicalism is<br />

equivalent to empiricism (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a priori versions) or that<br />

empirical access will not be def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> terms of ontological<br />

commitments of empirical <strong>the</strong>ories (possibly a posteriori). I<br />

suggest that “empiricism” <strong>and</strong> “physicalism,” are not to be<br />

equated; <strong>the</strong> second possibility boils down to add<strong>in</strong>g some<br />

explicit criteria for <strong>the</strong>ories that will be able to identify<br />

empirical objects. It seems that ei<strong>the</strong>r way, physicalism will<br />

have to say someth<strong>in</strong>g more specific about ideal <strong>the</strong>ories.<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> ways of spell<strong>in</strong>g out Hempel’s objection<br />

is to say that physicalists cannot ensure that <strong>the</strong> future<br />

ideal physics won’t <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong> term “ectoplasm,” or<br />

“nonmaterial substance” <strong>in</strong> its vocabulary. These terms<br />

would be worry<strong>in</strong>g for a physicalist because <strong>the</strong>y don’t<br />

seem to be reconcilable with <strong>the</strong> current physics.<br />

Currently, referr<strong>in</strong>g to ectoplasm boils down to stipulat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re be a miracle happen<strong>in</strong>g: There is no place for<br />

any entity like that <strong>in</strong> physical laws. Should <strong>the</strong>re be<br />

genu<strong>in</strong>e cognitive progress <strong>in</strong> physical <strong>the</strong>ories that leads<br />

to <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> term <strong>and</strong> appropriate laws to physics just<br />

<strong>the</strong> way o<strong>the</strong>r entities are admitted <strong>in</strong> scientific <strong>the</strong>ories,<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory-based physicalists would have to accept that. In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r words, as soon as ectoplasm is no longer a miracle<br />

<strong>in</strong> a <strong>the</strong>ory, it is not embarrass<strong>in</strong>g for physicalism. In spite<br />

of <strong>the</strong> skepticism about <strong>the</strong> cumulative nature of scientific<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories, it rema<strong>in</strong>s relatively uncontroversial that physics<br />

rema<strong>in</strong>s faithful to methodological naturalism. If this feature<br />

of science is relatively constant, <strong>the</strong>n we know enough<br />

about ideal physics to be able to refer it, as it won’t admit<br />

any supernatural objects. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, ideal <strong>the</strong>ories<br />

must fulfill <strong>the</strong> Humean prescription that explan<strong>and</strong>a<br />

cannot be more improbable than explanantes (famous<br />

section X of Hume 1902).<br />

Two th<strong>in</strong>gs might be observed. First, even ideal<br />

physics cannot be an absolutely complete <strong>the</strong>ory; it will<br />

never be free from cognitive constra<strong>in</strong>ts, such as <strong>in</strong>ability<br />

to observe <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite physical bodies at once by any f<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

cognitive agent. Second, <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sized complete<br />

physics will have limited power of expression; it could not<br />

decide logically undecidable problems, or problems that<br />

lead to comb<strong>in</strong>atorial explosion.<br />

227

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!