02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

32<br />

An Anti-<strong>Reduction</strong>ist Argument Based on Sp<strong>in</strong>oza’s Naturalism — Nancy Brenner-Golomb<br />

space.[Sp<strong>in</strong>oza 1979, p.7 (note to proposition X)]. The<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction, he expla<strong>in</strong>s, must be made only because none<br />

of <strong>the</strong>se ways of underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g can be derived from <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r. Tak<strong>in</strong>g an example from physics, <strong>in</strong>stead of his own<br />

[Sp<strong>in</strong>oza 1966, p.7], <strong>the</strong> abstract law of gravitation cannot<br />

be derived from observed movements alone, <strong>and</strong><br />

knowledge of this law is not sufficient for expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a<br />

particular movement <strong>in</strong> space. But <strong>the</strong> world <strong>the</strong>y expla<strong>in</strong> is<br />

clearly <strong>the</strong> same.<br />

Aga<strong>in</strong> we should note that although not many<br />

scientists or philosophers adhere to Cartesian dualism,<br />

Sp<strong>in</strong>oza’s argument is still relevant because this dualism<br />

has been replaced by a new one, namely of culture versus<br />

nature. Be<strong>in</strong>g beyond <strong>the</strong> permitted length of this paper, I<br />

can only po<strong>in</strong>t out that <strong>in</strong> spite of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence of Darw<strong>in</strong>,<br />

his followers only <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>the</strong> human body <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir study<br />

of evolution. And an <strong>in</strong>fluential scientist like Richard<br />

Dawk<strong>in</strong>s, or philosophers like Charles Peirce, Qu<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Daniel Dennett, among many o<strong>the</strong>rs, see<br />

<strong>in</strong> rational th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g a cultural <strong>in</strong>vention, where a culture is<br />

largely <strong>in</strong>dependent of nature. But by Sp<strong>in</strong>oza’s view a<br />

culture cannot be <strong>in</strong>dependent of nature. Anyth<strong>in</strong>g which<br />

can affect human behaviour must be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> natural<br />

terms because <strong>the</strong>re is noth<strong>in</strong>g outside nature.<br />

Sp<strong>in</strong>oza’s conception of substance is his conception<br />

of Nature as a whole. Its def<strong>in</strong>ition says that substance is<br />

its own cause <strong>and</strong> is to be conceived through itself, namely<br />

by noth<strong>in</strong>g outside itself [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza 1979 p.1, def<strong>in</strong>itions I<br />

<strong>and</strong> III], imply<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> laws of nature are not imposed<br />

by God on <strong>in</strong>ert matter, as Sp<strong>in</strong>oza's contemporaries, <strong>and</strong><br />

even Newton, believed. These def<strong>in</strong>itions say that <strong>the</strong> laws<br />

of nature express <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal dynamic force of material<br />

existence – which is <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g of his equat<strong>in</strong>g God to<br />

Nature, <strong>and</strong> that every th<strong>in</strong>g which comes <strong>in</strong>to existence is<br />

a modification of substance, <strong>and</strong> its own <strong>in</strong>ternal forces<br />

must be understood <strong>in</strong> terms of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal forces of<br />

Nature.<br />

In his Metaphysical Thoughts [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza 1998 p.120]<br />

Sp<strong>in</strong>oza argues that <strong>the</strong> essence of life should be<br />

understood as "<strong>the</strong> force through which th<strong>in</strong>gs persevere <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir own be<strong>in</strong>g." It is because this force can be<br />

conceptually dist<strong>in</strong>guished from <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong>mselves, he<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>s, that <strong>the</strong> idea arose that th<strong>in</strong>gs have life, namely<br />

souls, as if life was dist<strong>in</strong>ct from <strong>the</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves. In <strong>the</strong> Ethics he generalizes <strong>the</strong> idea to all<br />

structured th<strong>in</strong>gs. All th<strong>in</strong>gs, he says, behave so as to<br />

susta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own survival [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza, 1979 p.91 (proposition<br />

VI)].<br />

Comment<strong>in</strong>g on Descartes’ "I th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong>refore I<br />

am" Sp<strong>in</strong>oza says that Descartes <strong>in</strong>deed discovered an<br />

essence of man. But this essential feature is part of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>ternal forces by which people persevere <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir natural<br />

existence [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza 1998 pp.9-10]. Sp<strong>in</strong>oza expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong><br />

function of reason, as a corrective mechanism by which<br />

ideas are accepted or rejected by a balance of reasons,<br />

ak<strong>in</strong> to <strong>the</strong> balance of forces <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> body [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza 1979<br />

p.255]. He expla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> necessary <strong>in</strong>clusion of this<br />

mechanism <strong>in</strong> human nature as a result of his o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

explanation that <strong>the</strong> more a body can perceive <strong>and</strong><br />

respond to many th<strong>in</strong>gs at <strong>the</strong> same time, <strong>the</strong> more it<br />

depends on underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza 1979 p.48].<br />

This explanation is given <strong>in</strong> a note to proposition xiii<br />

<strong>in</strong> part II of <strong>the</strong> Ethics, which <strong>in</strong> a slightly different<br />

formulation says that an idea always reflects ei<strong>the</strong>r an<br />

objective state of <strong>the</strong> human body or a certa<strong>in</strong> mode of<br />

existence outside <strong>the</strong> body, <strong>and</strong> noth<strong>in</strong>g else [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza<br />

1979 p.47]. In order to underst<strong>and</strong> this proposition we may<br />

start by not<strong>in</strong>g that ‘ideas’ should be understood as<br />

<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g everyth<strong>in</strong>g of which we are conscious. For<br />

example, feel<strong>in</strong>g hungry is also an idea. The objective<br />

state, or as he says, <strong>the</strong> object of this idea, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> body is<br />

comparable to a biologist say<strong>in</strong>g that this feel<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>the</strong> set<br />

of processes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> body which produce it. A feel<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

clearly not <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong>se processes. But if it is what<br />

we are conscious of when certa<strong>in</strong> changes occurs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

body, <strong>in</strong> terms of which feel<strong>in</strong>g hungry is fully expla<strong>in</strong>ed. In<br />

this sense we may talk of a reduction of this mental state<br />

to a physical one. However, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Sp<strong>in</strong>oza, this<br />

explanation is not complete because a feel<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

categorized as a k<strong>in</strong>d of pa<strong>in</strong> – a general term describ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

transitional states of <strong>the</strong> body by which its power of action<br />

is reduced [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza 1979, p.128 (def<strong>in</strong>ition III <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

explanatory note)]. And it follows from his conception of<br />

life, that this feel<strong>in</strong>g must be comb<strong>in</strong>ed with a desire to<br />

restore <strong>the</strong> body to its natural capacities, which <strong>in</strong> this case<br />

means a desire to assuage <strong>the</strong> pa<strong>in</strong> of hunger.<br />

While <strong>the</strong> objective state <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> body underly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

feel<strong>in</strong>g hungry is a universal state reducible to biology, <strong>the</strong><br />

actual behaviour for restor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> body to its natural<br />

capacities depends on <strong>the</strong> knowledge how to do it. Hence,<br />

<strong>the</strong> objects of <strong>the</strong> ideas constitut<strong>in</strong>g this knowledge are<br />

‘certa<strong>in</strong> modes of extension actually exist<strong>in</strong>g’ outside <strong>the</strong><br />

body. This knowledge cannot be universal. If it were<br />

universal to our species, it would have meant that<br />

perception of <strong>the</strong>se objects outside <strong>the</strong> body toge<strong>the</strong>r with,<br />

as he says, <strong>the</strong> amaz<strong>in</strong>g laws of nature that move <strong>the</strong> body<br />

without <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d’s <strong>in</strong>terference, would have been sufficient<br />

for survival. And a <strong>the</strong>ory of m<strong>in</strong>d would be reducible to<br />

biology, even if environmental <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>in</strong>cludes learn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

by imitat<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r animals of <strong>the</strong> same species. In this<br />

case, <strong>the</strong> ‘bottom-up’ pr<strong>in</strong>ciple might have been saved.<br />

The reason why this is not so for human be<strong>in</strong>gs is that <strong>the</strong><br />

objects outside <strong>the</strong> body which affect behaviour are <strong>the</strong><br />

behaviours of o<strong>the</strong>r people whose desire is to live<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>ir natural drives.<br />

Aga<strong>in</strong>, Sp<strong>in</strong>oza’s naturalistic approach does not<br />

reject <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong> laws which govern a social<br />

structure emerge out of <strong>the</strong> properties of its elements,<br />

namely <strong>the</strong> properties of <strong>in</strong>dividual human be<strong>in</strong>gs. In <strong>the</strong><br />

first chapter of his Political Treatise he says that his<br />

<strong>in</strong>tention is to demonstrate that a sound political science<br />

can <strong>and</strong> ought to be based on what is known both of<br />

human nature <strong>and</strong> of political practice. This, accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

him, agrees with o<strong>the</strong>r branches of science which verify or<br />

reject <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>ories by available evidence. What his study<br />

of human nature taught him is that passions are stronger<br />

motives of behaviour than reason. It follows that when<br />

people <strong>in</strong> power design rules for preserv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tegrity of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir community, <strong>the</strong>y can never be free from <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence<br />

of <strong>the</strong>ir passions. Yet, he also learned that all people know<br />

that if <strong>the</strong>y want to pursue <strong>the</strong>ir own plans of life <strong>the</strong>y must<br />

surrender a great part of <strong>the</strong>ir power to <strong>the</strong> state [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza<br />

1951 pp.296-297 (15-16)]. This knowledge, accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

him, is not a result of us<strong>in</strong>g reason – as Hobbes argued at<br />

<strong>the</strong> time – but is an <strong>in</strong>tuition, which stated <strong>in</strong> modern terms<br />

means <strong>in</strong>nate knowledge, that we need each o<strong>the</strong>r’s help.<br />

People could not have discovered this essence of political<br />

life if <strong>the</strong>y were not already liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> societies [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza<br />

1966 p.269]. This he says, applies to all knowledge of a<br />

true essence of a th<strong>in</strong>g, even to ma<strong>the</strong>matics. We would<br />

not be able to know <strong>the</strong> essential equation of a parabola,<br />

for example, without first know<strong>in</strong>g parabolas. And we know<br />

parabolas because <strong>the</strong>y exist [Sp<strong>in</strong>oza 1998, p.99].<br />

Sp<strong>in</strong>oza expla<strong>in</strong>s that <strong>the</strong> basic political problem is<br />

not <strong>the</strong> imposition of law <strong>and</strong> order but <strong>the</strong> tendency of<br />

people <strong>in</strong> power to suppress <strong>the</strong> tendency of o<strong>the</strong>r people

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!