02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Structure of <strong>the</strong> Paradoxes, Structure of <strong>the</strong> Theories: A Logical<br />

Comparison of Set Theory <strong>and</strong> Semantics<br />

Giulia Terzian, Bristol, Engl<strong>and</strong>, UK<br />

1. Introduction<br />

F. Ramsey famously argued that <strong>the</strong> “logical” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> “semantical”<br />

paradoxes should be studied separately. Those<br />

of <strong>the</strong> first k<strong>in</strong>d “<strong>in</strong>volve only logical or ma<strong>the</strong>matical terms<br />

such as class <strong>and</strong> number, <strong>and</strong> show that <strong>the</strong>re must be<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g wrong with our logic or ma<strong>the</strong>matics”. On <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r side are those contradictions which “cannot be<br />

stated <strong>in</strong> logical terms alone, for <strong>the</strong>y all conta<strong>in</strong> some<br />

reference to thought, language, or symbolism, which are<br />

not formal but empirical terms.” (1925, p.353)<br />

With <strong>the</strong> development of modern set <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong><br />

semantics over <strong>the</strong> 20 th century, many have rejected this<br />

classification, argu<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>re is a unique shared<br />

structure underly<strong>in</strong>g most of <strong>the</strong> known paradoxes, <strong>and</strong><br />

that <strong>the</strong>refore a jo<strong>in</strong>t solution is also to be expected.<br />

Arguments to this effect can be found for <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>in</strong><br />

Herzberger 1970, Feferman 1984, Priest 1994; <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> next<br />

section, we will devote some attention to <strong>the</strong> second of<br />

<strong>the</strong>se papers.<br />

2. A simple sophisticated story<br />

In 1984, S. Feferman carries out a parallel reconstruction<br />

of Russell’s Paradox <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Liar Paradox, to show that<br />

both derive from <strong>the</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation of three features <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

background <strong>the</strong>ory:<br />

1. The language has enough syntactical resources<br />

to allow self-reference;<br />

2. Classical logic is assumed;<br />

3. The follow<strong>in</strong>g unrestricted schemes are respectively<br />

assumed as basic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples (for φ a formula<br />

of <strong>the</strong> language):<br />

(CA) ∃x∀y(y ∈ x ↔ φ[y])<br />

(TA) T( φ ) ↔ φ.<br />

Restriction of each of <strong>the</strong>se accord<strong>in</strong>gly corresponds to a<br />

possible solution strategy for <strong>the</strong> paradoxes. Russell <strong>and</strong><br />

Tarski pursued <strong>the</strong> first option, develop<strong>in</strong>g typed formalisms<br />

which “were early recognized to be excessively restrictive”<br />

(1984, p.75). To test <strong>the</strong> second strategy, Feferman<br />

constructs a common formalism for set <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong><br />

semantics, mak<strong>in</strong>g use of three-valued logical schemes<br />

(<strong>the</strong> primary references <strong>in</strong> semantics are of course Mart<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> Woodruff 1975, Kripke 1975). However <strong>the</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory is argued to be aga<strong>in</strong> too restrictive, <strong>in</strong>sofar as<br />

“noth<strong>in</strong>g like susta<strong>in</strong>ed ord<strong>in</strong>ary reason<strong>in</strong>g can be carried<br />

out <strong>in</strong> [three-valued] logic.” (p.95) But it should also be<br />

noted that restriction of logic does not constitute a st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

option for set <strong>the</strong>orists, <strong>and</strong> this on its own dim<strong>in</strong>ishes<br />

<strong>the</strong> prospects of obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a parallel solution of <strong>the</strong> paradoxes.<br />

The rest of <strong>the</strong> paper is <strong>the</strong>n devoted to <strong>the</strong> strategy<br />

of restrict<strong>in</strong>g basic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples: s<strong>in</strong>ce it has been successful<br />

<strong>in</strong> ZF <strong>the</strong>ory, where Russell’s paradox is blocked, <strong>the</strong> aim<br />

is to prove a similar result for semantics. Although this<br />

conjecture is not supported by a direct argument <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

paper, this can be made explicit as follows:<br />

(1) Set-<strong>the</strong>oretic <strong>and</strong> semantic paradoxes bear a<br />

structural similarity.<br />

(2) ZF set <strong>the</strong>ory is both a faithful account of set<br />

<strong>the</strong>orists' notion of set membership, <strong>and</strong> it successfully<br />

deals with <strong>the</strong> set-<strong>the</strong>oretic paradoxes.<br />

Therefore:<br />

(C) Any adequate solution to <strong>the</strong> semantic paradoxes<br />

is to be expected to bear a structural similarity<br />

to ZF set <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

A solution strategy for <strong>the</strong> paradoxes is a particular application<br />

of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical framework of set <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> semantics;<br />

thus acceptance of (C) is presumably dependent<br />

on <strong>the</strong> soundness of a more general argument which<br />

should show that a structural similarity holds between set<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> semantics <strong>the</strong>mselves. The upshot of <strong>the</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g<br />

account (hereafter analogy account) would be that<br />

set <strong>the</strong>ory can <strong>in</strong>form semantics <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> choice of <strong>the</strong> normative<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples which would underlie a successful (axiomatic)<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory of truth.<br />

Is <strong>the</strong> analogy account sound? If <strong>the</strong> paradoxes do<br />

have a jo<strong>in</strong>t solution <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby constitute evidence that a<br />

deeper analogy holds, <strong>the</strong>n a structural analogy ought<br />

surely to hold at <strong>the</strong> level of <strong>the</strong> foundations of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ories. Hence <strong>the</strong> first condition on accept<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

analogy account is that <strong>the</strong>re exist semantic counterparts<br />

of <strong>the</strong> normative pr<strong>in</strong>ciples underly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> choice of <strong>the</strong> ZF<br />

axioms.<br />

3 Why <strong>the</strong> ZF axioms?<br />

The literature is unanimous <strong>in</strong> identify<strong>in</strong>g two conceptions<br />

which enshr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> pre-<strong>the</strong>oretic <strong>in</strong>tuitions concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

notion of set, <strong>and</strong> which moreover acted both as motivations<br />

<strong>and</strong> normative constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> development of<br />

modern set <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

These are limitation of size <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> iterative<br />

conception:<br />

Remarks:<br />

(LIM) The axioms ought to entail that <strong>the</strong> setform<strong>in</strong>g<br />

operation applies to a collection of objects if<br />

<strong>and</strong> only if <strong>the</strong> collection is small enough; or more<br />

formally, if <strong>and</strong> only if its objects are not <strong>in</strong> one-one<br />

correspondence with all <strong>the</strong> objects of <strong>the</strong> universe<br />

of sets.<br />

(IT) The axioms ought to entail that a collection of<br />

objects is a set if <strong>and</strong> only if it is produced <strong>in</strong> a process<br />

of <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g sort: at stage 0 we have <strong>the</strong><br />

empty set Ø; at stage 1, Ø <strong>and</strong> its s<strong>in</strong>gleton set {Ø};<br />

<strong>and</strong> so on, <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> transf<strong>in</strong>ite; crucially, every set<br />

appears at some stage of this cumulative hierarchy.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard formalization:<br />

V0 = Ø; Vα+1 = P (Vα); Vγ = Uα

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!