02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Place of Theory <strong>Reduction</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Models of Interdiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary Relations — Uwe Voigt<br />

So far we have exam<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> “Yes”-branch of <strong>the</strong><br />

model of models of <strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary relations. But if we<br />

have to consider <strong>the</strong>ory reduction, it obviously is to be<br />

found on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side. The basic decision to be made,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n, is that <strong>the</strong>re are not irreducibly many discipl<strong>in</strong>es. If<br />

we decide this way, we do not face a problem of<br />

<strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary relations but ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> problem how to<br />

make <strong>the</strong> pseudo-problem of <strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary go away by<br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g all discipl<strong>in</strong>es collapse <strong>in</strong>to only one. So we are on<br />

<strong>the</strong> side of models which can be named as “monist”.<br />

The advantage of monist models is that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

guarantee – or at least claim to guarantee – a s<strong>in</strong>gle,<br />

univocal concept of science, based on <strong>the</strong> promised unity<br />

of science. At <strong>the</strong> same time, such models somehow have<br />

to deal with <strong>the</strong> (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir view apparent) plurality of<br />

discipl<strong>in</strong>es which even is <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g evermore (Poser<br />

2001, 279-287). Hence, monist models are challenged by<br />

<strong>the</strong> question: If <strong>the</strong>re is only one discipl<strong>in</strong>e, can <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

members of <strong>the</strong> apparent plurality of discipl<strong>in</strong>es be <strong>in</strong> some<br />

way identified with that one <strong>and</strong> only discipl<strong>in</strong>e? The<br />

answer “No” leads to elim<strong>in</strong>ative models, because given<br />

monist presuppositions non-identity with <strong>the</strong> one <strong>and</strong> only<br />

discipl<strong>in</strong>e just means be<strong>in</strong>g no scientific discipl<strong>in</strong>e at all. To<br />

elim<strong>in</strong>ate here means to demonstrate that <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d of<br />

objects with which a pseudo-discipl<strong>in</strong>e claims to deal<br />

simply do not exist <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong> term<strong>in</strong>ology used<br />

by that pseudo-discipl<strong>in</strong>e is mean<strong>in</strong>gless. This strategy can<br />

be – <strong>and</strong> has been – successful <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle cases, as e.g. <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> elim<strong>in</strong>ation of astrology from <strong>the</strong> realm of <strong>the</strong> sciences.<br />

The recent relevant discussion is focus<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> question<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r discipl<strong>in</strong>es of cognitive science can be elim<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

<strong>in</strong> favor of neurobiology <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al analysis of physics<br />

(e.g., as a classical attempt, Churchl<strong>and</strong> 1986). As an<br />

overall strategy for tackl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> problem of<br />

<strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>arity it is not very popular, though, because it<br />

flies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> face of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuition that <strong>the</strong>re are many<br />

discipl<strong>in</strong>es which at least have a partial <strong>and</strong> temporal<br />

justification (Charpa 1996, 96).<br />

Therefore <strong>the</strong> most promis<strong>in</strong>g answer <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> monist<br />

branch seems to be “Yes”: At least some members of <strong>the</strong><br />

apparent plurality of discipl<strong>in</strong>es can be identified with <strong>the</strong><br />

one <strong>and</strong> only discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong>, through this identification, are<br />

also justified. This is <strong>the</strong> strategy of <strong>the</strong>ory reduction which,<br />

as such, but without this context, is well researched <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

philosophy of science. Theory reduction can come along <strong>in</strong><br />

various k<strong>in</strong>ds, depend<strong>in</strong>g on which discipl<strong>in</strong>e one takes to<br />

be <strong>the</strong> goal of reduction. In our time, <strong>the</strong> most popular<br />

version is physicalist <strong>the</strong>ory reduction (Wilson 1998); but<br />

<strong>the</strong>re also is its sociological counterpart (Luhmann 1990),<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> list could be cont<strong>in</strong>ued. The f<strong>in</strong>al goal here, too, as<br />

<strong>in</strong> elim<strong>in</strong>ation always is to end up with just one scientific<br />

discipl<strong>in</strong>e, but before <strong>the</strong> goal is reached, <strong>the</strong> different<br />

exist<strong>in</strong>g discipl<strong>in</strong>es at least can be tolerated s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

differences from <strong>the</strong> one <strong>and</strong> only science are only<br />

apparent ones. Reductive models face similar problems as<br />

elim<strong>in</strong>ative ones: They also do not seem to do justice to<br />

<strong>the</strong> given plurality of discipl<strong>in</strong>es (Margolis 1987; Rosenberg<br />

1994). Never<strong>the</strong>less, this plurality is just a fact <strong>and</strong> facts<br />

can change. The hard problem of <strong>the</strong>ory reduction, <strong>in</strong> my<br />

view, seems to lie elsewhere, <strong>and</strong> can be found by a look<br />

at <strong>the</strong> whole model of models of <strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary relations.<br />

3. The Hard Problem of Theory <strong>Reduction</strong><br />

The hard problem of <strong>the</strong>ory reduction can be seen <strong>in</strong> its<br />

contrast to <strong>the</strong> cooperation-contact models which are <strong>the</strong><br />

most important plural models: Contact-models, as has<br />

been shown, imply mutual recognition between <strong>the</strong> cooperat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

discipl<strong>in</strong>es. This recognition is withdrawn by monist<br />

models. Elim<strong>in</strong>ative models do so immediately, which<br />

makes <strong>the</strong>m so little attractive. Reductive models are more<br />

cautious <strong>in</strong> this respect, <strong>the</strong>y even promise to give a special<br />

discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> dignity of <strong>the</strong> one <strong>and</strong> only discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> way of identification. But this identification is a one-way<br />

affair. The identity of <strong>the</strong> goal-discipl<strong>in</strong>e of reduction is<br />

supposed to be unchang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> well-known; <strong>the</strong> identity of<br />

<strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e which is to be reduced just is an apparent<br />

one; it has been falsely taken to be someth<strong>in</strong>g apart from<br />

<strong>the</strong> one <strong>and</strong> only science. So, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> recognition of a <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

which is to be reduced, <strong>the</strong> goal-<strong>the</strong>ory of reduction simply<br />

recognizes itself <strong>in</strong> a disguise which soon is to be removed.<br />

However, as Hegel has shown throughout his<br />

Phenomenology of Spirit, recognition from its very concept<br />

always must be mutual; it presupposes two parties recogniz<strong>in</strong>g<br />

one ano<strong>the</strong>r. This problem is gett<strong>in</strong>g even harder as<br />

we tend to take for real only what science tells us to be<br />

real (Qu<strong>in</strong>e 1979). So, if <strong>the</strong>re is only one scientific discipl<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

no one can recognize it as such, nei<strong>the</strong>r from <strong>the</strong><br />

outside – for only science has <strong>the</strong> authority to do so – nor<br />

from <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>side – for <strong>the</strong>re can be no mutuality here. The<br />

hard problem of <strong>the</strong>ory reduction, at least as a global<br />

strategy fac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> problem of <strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>arity, <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

is: If it is successful, it leads to a situation <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong><br />

supposed one <strong>and</strong> only discipl<strong>in</strong>e can get no recognition at<br />

all. Hence, contact models, <strong>and</strong> especially cooperationcontact<br />

models do not only seem to be a better description<br />

of <strong>the</strong> reality of science <strong>in</strong> our days; <strong>the</strong>y also seem to be a<br />

better way to deal with <strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>arity without endanger<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole concept of science as such.<br />

Literature<br />

Bourdieu, Pierre 1988: Homo academicus, Frankfurt am Ma<strong>in</strong><br />

Carrier, Mart<strong>in</strong> 2006: Wissenschafts<strong>the</strong>orie zur E<strong>in</strong>führung. Hamburg<br />

Chalmers, Alan F. 5 2001: Wege der Wissenschaft. E<strong>in</strong>führung <strong>in</strong><br />

die Wissenschafts<strong>the</strong>orie. Berl<strong>in</strong> etc.<br />

Charpa Ulrich 1996: Grundprobleme der Wissenschaftsphilosophie.<br />

Paderborn etc.<br />

Churchl<strong>and</strong>, Paul M. 1986: Neurophilosophy. Toward a Unified<br />

Science of <strong>the</strong> M<strong>in</strong>d-Bra<strong>in</strong>. Cambridge, Mass. etc.<br />

Hack<strong>in</strong>g, Ian 1996: E<strong>in</strong>führung <strong>in</strong> die Philosophie der Naturwissenschaften.<br />

Stuttgart<br />

Fauser, Markus 2003: E<strong>in</strong>führung <strong>in</strong> die Kulturwissenschaft. Darmstadt<br />

Feyerabend, Paul 1983: Wider den Methodenzwang. Frankfurt am<br />

Ma<strong>in</strong><br />

Gläser, Jochen et al.: “E<strong>in</strong>leitung: Heterogene Kooperation”, <strong>in</strong>:<br />

Jörg Strüb<strong>in</strong>g et al. (eds.), Kooperation im Niem<strong>and</strong>sl<strong>and</strong>. Neue<br />

Perspektiven auf Zusammenarbeit <strong>in</strong> Wissenschaft und Technik,<br />

Opladen 2004, pp. 7-24<br />

Luhmann, Niklas 1990: Die Wissenschaft der Gesellschaft. Frankfurt<br />

am Ma<strong>in</strong><br />

Margolis, Joseph 1987: The Persistence of Reality. Science Without<br />

Unity. Reconcil<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Human <strong>and</strong> Natural <strong>Sciences</strong>. Oxford-<br />

New York<br />

369

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!