02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

of <strong>the</strong> world. It only matters that certa<strong>in</strong> structural features<br />

are modelled, such as <strong>in</strong>teraction between <strong>the</strong> parts of a<br />

multi-agent system or <strong>the</strong> possibility of strategy change.<br />

Once <strong>the</strong>se features are <strong>in</strong>corporated, <strong>the</strong> employed<br />

microscopic models of f<strong>in</strong>ancial markets may be<br />

surpris<strong>in</strong>gly unrealistic <strong>in</strong> various o<strong>the</strong>r features. For<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance, microscopic models of f<strong>in</strong>ancial markets abstract<br />

from material details about traders <strong>and</strong> transactions that<br />

are considered as irrelevant for underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> basic<br />

features of f<strong>in</strong>ancial markets (‘Aristotelian idealization’).<br />

But microscopic models of f<strong>in</strong>ancial markets also <strong>in</strong>volve<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> distortions, which simplify <strong>the</strong> situation considerably<br />

(‘Galilean idealization’). Moreover, play<strong>in</strong>g around with<br />

numerous different more or less unrealistic models has <strong>the</strong><br />

advantage that it is possible to s<strong>in</strong>gle out exactly which<br />

structural mechanisms are responsible for <strong>the</strong> statistical<br />

effects one wants to expla<strong>in</strong> (see Morgan 1999 for a<br />

related conclusion). In contrast, an approach with a<br />

detailed realistic model might not reveal what it is that is<br />

actually crucial for <strong>the</strong> explanation (cf. Wimsatt 1987 <strong>and</strong><br />

Cartwright 1983). My po<strong>in</strong>t is that agent-based models<br />

help to expla<strong>in</strong> by concentrat<strong>in</strong>g on significant structural<br />

features while <strong>the</strong>re is hardly any pretence to realism <strong>in</strong><br />

many o<strong>the</strong>r respects. Batterman (2004) has a similar po<strong>in</strong>t,<br />

when he argues that highly idealized <strong>and</strong> oversimplified<br />

models can sometimes be better for <strong>the</strong> explanation of <strong>the</strong><br />

dom<strong>in</strong>ant phenomenon than a detailed model <strong>in</strong> terms of<br />

micro-constituents.<br />

3. Complexity <strong>and</strong> Robust Mechanisms <strong>in</strong><br />

Agent-Based Models<br />

Roughly, I underst<strong>and</strong> a complex system not as an object<br />

with a complicated compositional structure but ra<strong>the</strong>r as an<br />

object with highly non-trivial dynamical features, on <strong>the</strong><br />

basis of a structurally simple arrangement of a large number<br />

of non-l<strong>in</strong>early <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g constituents. One example is<br />

dynamical multi-agent systems <strong>in</strong> socio-economic contexts,<br />

which deal with ‘microscopic’ agents <strong>in</strong> a very simple<br />

arrangement <strong>and</strong> with a very simple <strong>in</strong>dividual behaviour.<br />

Whereas for a classical mechanism it is usually easy to<br />

predict its behaviour once <strong>the</strong> compositional structure <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> behaviour of its parts is known, this is radically different<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of complex systems. Here <strong>the</strong> knowledge of <strong>the</strong><br />

compositional structure, e.g. sp<strong>in</strong>s on a square lattice,<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> knowledge of <strong>the</strong> behaviour of its parts <strong>in</strong><br />

isolation as well as <strong>in</strong> simple composites, allows for hardly<br />

any straightforward predictions of <strong>the</strong> dynamical behaviour<br />

of <strong>the</strong> complex system.<br />

Although higher-level <strong>in</strong>teractions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby<br />

higher-level mechanisms are ultimately ontologically<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> underly<strong>in</strong>g physics, higher-level<br />

mechanisms are explanatorily autonomous. For <strong>in</strong>stance, if<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ancial market crashes were described <strong>in</strong> terms of <strong>the</strong><br />

material processes that obta<strong>in</strong> between <strong>in</strong>vestors <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

telephones, traders <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir computers, electronic<br />

processes with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> computer system of <strong>the</strong> NASDAQ<br />

etc., <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> mechanisms <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> a crash could never<br />

be appropriately understood. As it turns out it is sensible to<br />

abstract so much from <strong>the</strong>se material manifestations that it<br />

is possible to realize that <strong>the</strong> same mechanisms obta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r contexts, notably <strong>in</strong> statistical physics (see Kuhlmann<br />

2006). These consideration show that it can be extremely<br />

important for explanations, <strong>in</strong> particular for explanations <strong>in</strong><br />

terms of mechanisms, not to elim<strong>in</strong>ate level-specific<br />

vocabulary, notions <strong>and</strong> methods.<br />

For mechanistic explanations <strong>in</strong> agent-based<br />

complex systems, <strong>the</strong> occurrence of <strong>the</strong> type of dynamical<br />

Reduc<strong>in</strong>g Complexity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Sciences</strong> — Me<strong>in</strong>ard Kuhlmann<br />

higher-level pattern one wants to expla<strong>in</strong>, e.g. a statistical<br />

phenomenon, must be robust. The qualification type of<br />

pattern is essential s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> complex systems <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

tokens of a dynamical pattern are usually not robust due to<br />

<strong>the</strong> high sensitivity to variations of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial conditions. In<br />

contrast to a classical mechanism like a <strong>the</strong>rmostat, from<br />

which we expect a predictable output <strong>in</strong> each s<strong>in</strong>gle case<br />

of its work<strong>in</strong>g, mechanisms <strong>in</strong> complex systems mostly do<br />

not generate token outcomes that we can predict, but<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r br<strong>in</strong>g about a certa<strong>in</strong> type of outcome. But when it<br />

comes to <strong>the</strong> explanation of statistical features, <strong>the</strong><br />

sensitivity to variations of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial conditions <strong>in</strong> each<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle case dissolves <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> collective statistics, which is<br />

not sensitive to such perturbations, provided <strong>the</strong><br />

explanation is successful. To put it <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around: a<br />

mechanistic explanation of a statistical phenomenon <strong>in</strong> a<br />

complex system is only successful if <strong>the</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g collective<br />

statistics of many simulation runs is not sensitive to<br />

perturbations of <strong>the</strong> system’s parameters <strong>in</strong> a reasonable<br />

range of values. If this condition were not fulfilled one<br />

would ra<strong>the</strong>r classify <strong>the</strong> phenomenon as an artefact of <strong>the</strong><br />

model, which does not help to identify an explanatory<br />

mechanism.<br />

4. Structural Mechanisms<br />

The above considerations show that a more abstract structural<br />

conception of mechanisms is prerequisite for underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

explanations <strong>in</strong> complex systems <strong>the</strong>ories. The<br />

notion of mechanisms I want to suggest applies to many<br />

cases <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> social sciences but also <strong>in</strong> physics, <strong>and</strong> biology,<br />

as far as <strong>the</strong>y are complex systems <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense I<br />

specified abobe. Currently, mechanisms are often discussed<br />

on <strong>the</strong> basis of case studies about biological systems<br />

(see e.g. Machamer, Darden, <strong>and</strong> Craver 2000).<br />

Naturally, this br<strong>in</strong>gs about limitations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> applicability. I<br />

propose <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g more general notion of a mechanism<br />

<strong>in</strong> a complex system:<br />

A property of <strong>the</strong> time-dependent relation between<br />

locally <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g lower-level components <strong>and</strong> a<br />

higher-level quantity of a complex system is a c<strong>and</strong>idate<br />

for a mechanism if it fulfils <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g requirements:<br />

(i) The dynamics of <strong>the</strong> higher-level<br />

quantity exhibits a discernible type of pattern, which<br />

we want to be expla<strong>in</strong>ed. (ii) The occurrence of this<br />

type of higher-level pattern is robust, i.e. it rema<strong>in</strong>s<br />

qualitatively <strong>the</strong> same under small variations of<br />

lower-level quantities.<br />

My emphasis on <strong>the</strong> local nature of <strong>in</strong>teraction is meant <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g way. If <strong>the</strong> occurrence of <strong>the</strong> higher-level<br />

pattern was due to an external <strong>in</strong>fluence with a global effect,<br />

e.g. a coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g external force on all constituents,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n I th<strong>in</strong>k one should not say that <strong>the</strong> higher-level pattern<br />

was generated by a mechanism. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong><br />

higher-level pattern must emerge purely out of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction<br />

of <strong>the</strong> system’s constituents.<br />

I want to illustrate my characterisation of mechanisms<br />

<strong>in</strong> complex systems for <strong>the</strong> above-mentioned multiagent<br />

model by Lux <strong>and</strong> Marchesi. The higher-level quantity<br />

is <strong>the</strong> price of some asset, e.g. a stock, currency or<br />

bond, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>g example for <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g<br />

lower-level components are traders <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> respective f<strong>in</strong>ancial<br />

market. An example for a discernible pattern <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

dynamics of this higher-level quantity is <strong>the</strong> so-called ‘volatility<br />

cluster<strong>in</strong>g’, i.e. <strong>the</strong> tendency of quiet <strong>and</strong> turbulent (or<br />

‘volatile’) periods to cluster toge<strong>the</strong>r. The agent-based<br />

explanation of this phenomenon rests on idealized assumptions<br />

about <strong>the</strong> relation between <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g lower-<br />

191

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!