02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Scepticism, Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>'s H<strong>in</strong>ge Propositions,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Common Ground<br />

Erik Stei, Ma<strong>in</strong>z, Germany<br />

1. Introduction<br />

Traditionally, systematic scepticism states that know<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

cont<strong>in</strong>gent proposition p, e. g., that I have h<strong>and</strong>s, entails<br />

that I know <strong>the</strong> denial of a sceptical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (sh), e. g.,<br />

that I am a bra<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> a vat. Because sh is usually formulated<br />

<strong>in</strong> a way that apparently makes it impossible for me to<br />

know its denial on basis of my evidence, it seems as if I do<br />

not know p. More formally, <strong>the</strong> sceptical argument looks<br />

like this 1 :<br />

334<br />

(1) a. K(S, p) → K(S, ¬sh)<br />

b. ¬K(S, ¬sh)<br />

c. ¬K(S, p)<br />

The notorious Moorean response is to make <strong>the</strong> sceptical<br />

modus tollens a modus ponens by affirm<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> antecedent<br />

of (1a) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second step of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ference, conclud<strong>in</strong>g<br />

K(S, ¬sh). Effectively, if we want to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> epistemic<br />

closure, (1b) seems to be <strong>the</strong> crucial step. However, which<br />

premise we assume—K(S, p) or ¬K(S, ¬sh)—certa<strong>in</strong>ly<br />

needs some fur<strong>the</strong>r justification. The problem is that <strong>in</strong> an<br />

epistemology classroom <strong>the</strong> sceptic’s story sounds just as<br />

plausible as our ord<strong>in</strong>ary knowledge-claims, which seems<br />

to leave us <strong>in</strong> an epistemically underdeterm<strong>in</strong>ed situation.<br />

However, I follow Williams’s (2003) conjecture that<br />

<strong>the</strong> justification of ei<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> two propositions depends<br />

(at least <strong>in</strong> part) on <strong>the</strong> question which o<strong>the</strong>r propositions<br />

we (tacitly) accept <strong>in</strong> a given context. It is Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

notion of h<strong>in</strong>ge propositions that underp<strong>in</strong>s this thought.<br />

2. H<strong>in</strong>ge propositions<br />

The metaphor of h<strong>in</strong>ges (HP) goes back to a famous paragraph<br />

<strong>in</strong> On Certa<strong>in</strong>ty, <strong>in</strong> which it is employed to illustrate<br />

<strong>the</strong> necessity of accept<strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> propositions <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

make sense of doubt<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>rs:<br />

“That is to say, <strong>the</strong> questions that we raise <strong>and</strong> our<br />

doubts depend on <strong>the</strong> fact that some propositions<br />

are exempt from doubt, are as it were like h<strong>in</strong>ges on<br />

which those turn.”<br />

(Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> 1984: 186 – § 341) 2<br />

Thus if “I make an experiment I do not doubt <strong>the</strong> existence<br />

of <strong>the</strong> apparatus before my eyes. I have plenty of doubts,<br />

but not that” (Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> 1984: 185). This, however, does<br />

not mean that <strong>the</strong>re is a rigid set of self-evident propositions,<br />

i. e., Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> does not advocate a strictly foundationalist<br />

conception of justification. This is quite obvious<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g paragraph:<br />

1 Where knowledge is symbolized by a two-place relation K, tak<strong>in</strong>g an epistemic<br />

subject S <strong>and</strong> a proposition (p or sh) as arguments. I will disregard time<br />

<strong>in</strong> this paper.<br />

2 Translation of Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> quotes by Denis Paul <strong>and</strong> G. E. M. Anscombe,<br />

as found on http://budni.by.ru/oncerta<strong>in</strong>ty.html on March, 20th, 2008<br />

“But it isn’t that <strong>the</strong> situation is like this: We just can’t<br />

<strong>in</strong>vestigate everyth<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> for that reason we are<br />

forced to rest content with assumption. If I want <strong>the</strong><br />

door to turn, <strong>the</strong> h<strong>in</strong>ges must stay put.”<br />

(Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> 1984: 187 – § 343)<br />

Now, how could <strong>the</strong>se ideas help us with respect to <strong>the</strong><br />

sceptical problem? A first rough answer is that i) which<br />

proposition we are justified <strong>in</strong> assum<strong>in</strong>g as our second<br />

premise (1b) depends on certa<strong>in</strong> HP <strong>and</strong> that ii) <strong>the</strong>se HP<br />

<strong>in</strong> turn depend on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>quiry we are <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong>. Thus,<br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s remarks seem to support <strong>the</strong> idea that a<br />

given knowledge claim might vary <strong>in</strong> truth value, depend<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on which HP we accept <strong>in</strong> a conversational context or<br />

<strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> circumstances of evaluation. 3 If this is correct,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> notion of HP might streng<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis<br />

that knowledge claims are sensitive to contextual factors <strong>in</strong><br />

a wider sense.<br />

3. Sceptical Presuppositions<br />

Before go<strong>in</strong>g on, let me briefly sketch ano<strong>the</strong>r important<br />

feature of this view. One dubious po<strong>in</strong>t often made <strong>in</strong> favour<br />

of <strong>the</strong> sceptic is <strong>the</strong> Cartesian claim that scepticism<br />

operates <strong>in</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d of neutral context <strong>and</strong> does not rely<br />

on any axioms or assumptions. If this were true <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong><br />

sceptic would <strong>in</strong> fact be <strong>in</strong> a privileged position. However,<br />

Williams 2007 offers many arguments for <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t that this<br />

claim is <strong>in</strong> fact a platitude, argu<strong>in</strong>g that scepticism does<br />

<strong>in</strong>deed depend on certa<strong>in</strong> assumptions or HP. Many philosophers<br />

from quite a diverse range of positions seem to<br />

share at least <strong>the</strong> spirit of this view. From a methodological<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t of view, Timothy Williamson highlights that “<strong>the</strong> sceptic<br />

relies uncritically on rules of dialectical engagement<br />

(…), without question<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir appropriateness to <strong>the</strong> radical<br />

questions which scepticism raises” (Williamson 2000:<br />

188). Ano<strong>the</strong>r po<strong>in</strong>t, addressed by Barry Stroud (Stroud<br />

2000), could be <strong>the</strong> (traditional) philosopher’s wish to give<br />

a completely general account of knowledge. However,<br />

even if this general k<strong>in</strong>d of knowledge is not available to us<br />

it does not follow that we cannot have any more specific<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d of knowledge. Still ano<strong>the</strong>r presupposition of <strong>the</strong><br />

sceptic is that our perceptions are <strong>in</strong>dependent of how <strong>the</strong><br />

world really is <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs we assign to words<br />

<strong>and</strong> propositions are <strong>in</strong> our heads only. It is due to this<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternalist worry that scepticism seems so conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g, but<br />

that is no reason for accept<strong>in</strong>g it. There is of course much<br />

more to be said on this topic, but let me adhere without<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r argument, rely<strong>in</strong>g on Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, that <strong>the</strong>re must<br />

be someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> sceptic takes for granted <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

make sense of her worries <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place.<br />

Obviously, this analysis only transfers <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

of underdeterm<strong>in</strong>acy to a meta-level. To see this, let us<br />

grant for <strong>the</strong> moment that accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> above picture<br />

<strong>the</strong> justification for assum<strong>in</strong>g, say, (1b) is that it can be<br />

derived from a set of HP operative <strong>in</strong> a given context. We<br />

3 I am deliberately vague on <strong>the</strong> mechanisms yield<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> truth-value of<br />

knowledge claims as I do not want to enter <strong>the</strong> debate between Contextualism<br />

<strong>and</strong> Subject Sensitive Invariantism. What is important here, however, is that<br />

both views hold that a given knowledge claim can vary <strong>in</strong> truth-value.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!