02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Supervenience <strong>and</strong> ‘Should’<br />

Arto Siitonen, Hels<strong>in</strong>ki, F<strong>in</strong>l<strong>and</strong><br />

Introduction<br />

Concern<strong>in</strong>g any entity or any fact, we may wonder how<br />

does it fit <strong>in</strong>to reality as a whole. We thus raise questions<br />

of <strong>the</strong> type: What is <strong>the</strong> place of – <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> scheme of reality?<br />

As <strong>the</strong> placeholders for '–' we may put stars, atoms, populations,<br />

societies, histories, human be<strong>in</strong>gs, languages,<br />

works of art, numbers etc. These are mutually related <strong>in</strong> a<br />

variety of ways. In order to account for those multifarious<br />

relations, we organize <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>to a system. The guid<strong>in</strong>g<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of such an organization is that th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> facts<br />

are not disconnected but depend on each o<strong>the</strong>r. Certa<strong>in</strong><br />

entities <strong>and</strong> occurrences depend for <strong>the</strong>ir existence on<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r entities <strong>and</strong> occurrences. We are dependent<br />

for our existence on our ancestors; we are connected to<br />

<strong>the</strong>m through causal l<strong>in</strong>es of heredity. There is also a more<br />

conceptual k<strong>in</strong>d of dependence: for <strong>in</strong>stance, to be sentient<br />

depends on be<strong>in</strong>g alive – non-liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs cannot be<br />

sentient be<strong>in</strong>gs. Stones do not perceive, let alone th<strong>in</strong>k.<br />

This dependence has been expressed <strong>in</strong> philosophy<br />

by say<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> property 'sentient' supervenes on <strong>the</strong><br />

property 'alive', or <strong>the</strong> fact 'a is a sentient be<strong>in</strong>g' supervenes<br />

on <strong>the</strong> fact 'a is a liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g'. Supervenience<br />

means dependence, determ<strong>in</strong>ation, <strong>and</strong> necessary condition;<br />

to <strong>the</strong>se relations are added <strong>the</strong> claims of reducibility<br />

<strong>and</strong> expla<strong>in</strong>ability. A superven<strong>in</strong>g property or fact can be<br />

reduced to <strong>the</strong> property or fact on which it supervenes; <strong>and</strong><br />

by that, it is expla<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> latter. Reducibility claim<br />

means that <strong>the</strong> former is to be "noth<strong>in</strong>g but" <strong>the</strong> latter, organized<br />

<strong>in</strong> a proper way. An adequate explanation makes<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>able why this is so.<br />

We may extract from <strong>the</strong> forego<strong>in</strong>g consideration <strong>the</strong><br />

question: Could – be removed without remov<strong>in</strong>g –<br />

<strong>the</strong>reby? If not, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> latter is a necessary precondition<br />

of <strong>the</strong> former; thus, for <strong>in</strong>stance, be<strong>in</strong>g alive is required for<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g sentient. This gives a partial answer to <strong>the</strong> above<br />

question of <strong>the</strong> "place of –" <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> scheme of nature, <strong>in</strong><br />

respect to <strong>the</strong> facts <strong>and</strong> properties concerned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> example.<br />

If supervenience is a thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g universal factor<br />

<strong>in</strong> reality – <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> our account of reality –, <strong>the</strong>n it sounds<br />

reasonable to extend its sphere from nature to culture.<br />

Here reductive explanation meets some challenges. Sport<br />

clubs, societies, states, etc. may be reducible to psychology<br />

– <strong>and</strong> by this, all <strong>the</strong> way down to physics. Concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

numbers, <strong>the</strong>y are conceptual entities that may be reducible<br />

to logic (cf. <strong>the</strong> logicist program of Frege <strong>and</strong> Russell),<br />

but presumably not to count<strong>in</strong>g, or to any o<strong>the</strong>r actions. As<br />

to works of art, one may claim that, e.g., a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g is reducible<br />

to <strong>the</strong> composition of its <strong>in</strong>gredients, i.e., colour<br />

spots on a canvas, or an orchestral work to <strong>the</strong> sound<br />

waves that vibrate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> air <strong>in</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> way, etc. However,<br />

<strong>the</strong> question of <strong>the</strong>ir aes<strong>the</strong>tic value is a harder one: would<br />

not <strong>the</strong> value that <strong>the</strong>y have, exceed <strong>the</strong> evaluations given<br />

to <strong>the</strong>m by various persons? Correspond<strong>in</strong>gly, common<br />

morality may be reducible to social <strong>and</strong> psychological<br />

facts, but what about <strong>the</strong> claims that be<strong>in</strong>g moral presents<br />

to us – are not <strong>the</strong>se irreducible?<br />

Let us focus on <strong>the</strong> issue of values <strong>and</strong> norms.<br />

Above, properties <strong>and</strong> facts were considered as superven<strong>in</strong>g<br />

entities. Among facts belong actions performed by<br />

human be<strong>in</strong>gs. Evaluat<strong>in</strong>g, esteem<strong>in</strong>g, comm<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

requir<strong>in</strong>g are human actions. If <strong>the</strong> idea of supervenience<br />

is pursued consistently, <strong>the</strong>se actions are traced back to<br />

facts concern<strong>in</strong>g nervous systems of organisms, <strong>and</strong> subsequently<br />

all <strong>the</strong> way through to <strong>the</strong> undulations of elementary<br />

particles.<br />

However, are <strong>the</strong> very values <strong>and</strong> norms thus reduced?<br />

Challeng<strong>in</strong>g this, one may appeal to <strong>the</strong> gap between<br />

'is' <strong>and</strong> 'ought', as seen by David Hume. It may be<br />

that values <strong>and</strong> norms are not accountable by supervenience.<br />

Or, if <strong>the</strong>y are, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y are reducible to facts –<br />

facts organized <strong>in</strong> a proper way, whatever that may be.<br />

Examples of such facts can be certa<strong>in</strong> features <strong>in</strong> works of<br />

art, <strong>in</strong> human actions, <strong>in</strong> society. One may also try to base<br />

values <strong>and</strong> obligations on acts of esteem<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> requir<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Hume did not exclude <strong>the</strong> possibility of account<strong>in</strong>g 'ought'<br />

through 'is'; he just raised <strong>the</strong> question of how <strong>the</strong> production<br />

of an 'ought' from an 'is' is achieved, <strong>and</strong> justified.<br />

Below, <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>sis will be defended: it is<br />

questionable whe<strong>the</strong>r values <strong>and</strong> norms sui generis are<br />

reductively expla<strong>in</strong>able – <strong>and</strong> thus, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y supervene<br />

on facts. This worry arises due to <strong>the</strong> 'is/ought'-gap.<br />

1. Supervenience account<strong>in</strong>g for facts<br />

We construct systems of science with <strong>the</strong>ir branch<strong>in</strong>g subsystems;<br />

<strong>and</strong> we claim that such a system adequately<br />

represents reality. Thus, <strong>the</strong>re is "<strong>the</strong> real order of th<strong>in</strong>gs"<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> order that we make <strong>in</strong> order to account for that (cf.<br />

title of Mol<strong>and</strong>er (1982)). This is <strong>the</strong> basis for <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

between reality <strong>and</strong> research of reality.<br />

The idea of supervenience is concerned with <strong>the</strong><br />

order <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> order<strong>in</strong>g of facts. It makes ontological<br />

<strong>and</strong> epistemological commitments. It classifies facts<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to certa<strong>in</strong> evolutionary pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> a<br />

comprehensive way. 'Supervenience' is a philosophical<br />

concept that is applied to <strong>the</strong> methods <strong>and</strong> results of<br />

science. Francis Crick, although not employ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

of supervenience, considers <strong>the</strong> neurobiological account of<br />

consciousness as a scientific hypo<strong>the</strong>sis; cf. his work<br />

(1994). On his view of <strong>the</strong> relation between science <strong>and</strong><br />

philosophy, cf. p. 256 ff of that work. He hopes that<br />

"philosophers will learn enough about <strong>the</strong> bra<strong>in</strong> to suggest<br />

ideas about how it works" (p. 258).<br />

Build<strong>in</strong>g up classificatory schemata <strong>and</strong> subsum<strong>in</strong>g<br />

various occurrences under <strong>the</strong>m is <strong>the</strong> first, basic task of<br />

scientific research. Carl von L<strong>in</strong>né accomplished this <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

area of botany; cf. especially his work 'Species plantarum'<br />

from 1753. He also contributed to <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>g<br />

organiz<strong>in</strong>g work <strong>in</strong> zoology. These studies were<br />

complemented by researchers who worked on anatomy,<br />

physiology <strong>and</strong> ecology. A new question was raised <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

studies on heredity, <strong>and</strong> it was Charles Darw<strong>in</strong> who gave<br />

<strong>the</strong> explanation to this phenomenon by <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of<br />

evolution (cf. his work 'The Orig<strong>in</strong> of Species by Means of<br />

Natural Selection', 1859). F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>the</strong> basic factor of life,<br />

<strong>the</strong> genetic code, was unravelled by Francis Crick <strong>and</strong><br />

James D. Watson <strong>in</strong> 1953. This discovery revealed <strong>the</strong> role<br />

of nucleic acids <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> generation <strong>and</strong> growth of liv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

be<strong>in</strong>gs. It thus identified <strong>the</strong> physical basis of life.<br />

321

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!