02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Counterfactuals, Ontological Commitment <strong>and</strong> Arithmetic<br />

Paul McCallion, St Andrews, Scotl<strong>and</strong>, UK<br />

1.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> face of it, utterances of arithmetic sentences <strong>in</strong><br />

which number words or numerals occur as s<strong>in</strong>gular terms<br />

carry commitment to <strong>the</strong> existence of numbers. Yet <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

no easy path from <strong>the</strong> syntax of an uttered sentence to a<br />

claim about ontological commitment. For it might be that<br />

<strong>the</strong> sentence is uttered with non-assertoric force, for example<br />

as <strong>in</strong> make-believe. Alternatively, it might be that <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence is to be understood non-literally.<br />

An assignment of ontological commitment to an<br />

utterance should mesh with <strong>the</strong> beliefs that may be<br />

reasonably attributed to <strong>the</strong> speaker (for a brief discussion<br />

of <strong>the</strong> case of applied arithmetic see (Rayo forthcom<strong>in</strong>g)).<br />

It would, for <strong>in</strong>stance, be implausible to attribute a<br />

commitment to <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong> average Scot to<br />

someone who asserts<br />

216<br />

(1) The average Scot has 2.3 children,<br />

because, for one th<strong>in</strong>g, it is implausible to suppose that <strong>the</strong><br />

speaker believes that any Scot has a non-natural number<br />

of children.<br />

In (Yablo 2001) it is noted that <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness of<br />

speakers to assert<br />

(2) The number of moons of Jupiter is four<br />

seems to turn on whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y believe that Jupiter has<br />

exactly four moons, <strong>and</strong> is apparently <strong>in</strong>dependent of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

belief <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence of arithmetical objects. There is<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore a prima facie case for deny<strong>in</strong>g that an utterance<br />

of (2) carries commitment to <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong> number<br />

four, just as an utterance of (1) does not carry commitment<br />

to <strong>the</strong> average Scot.<br />

Yablo suggests that sentences such as (2) are<br />

uttered with non-assertoric force, as part of <strong>the</strong> pretence<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re are numbers. An alternative explanation is that<br />

utterances of (2) are to be understood non-literally. On that<br />

view, <strong>the</strong> surface syntax of (2) is mislead<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> it is used<br />

to express <strong>the</strong> proposition that<br />

(3) Jupiter has exactly four moons<br />

An attractive feature of both Yablo’s suggestion <strong>and</strong> of <strong>the</strong><br />

alternative just mentioned is that <strong>the</strong>y promise to remove<br />

<strong>the</strong> difficulties surround<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> epistemology of ma<strong>the</strong>matical<br />

objects. One might <strong>the</strong>refore ask whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se analyses<br />

can be extended to pure arithmetic, for pure arithmetic<br />

is replete with numerical s<strong>in</strong>gular terms. The aim of this<br />

paper is to <strong>in</strong>vestigate whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> latter analysis can be<br />

so extended (for an extension of <strong>the</strong> pretence view to pure<br />

arithmetic <strong>and</strong> set <strong>the</strong>ory, see (Yablo 2005)).<br />

The surface syntax of simple arithmetic sums (such<br />

as ‘5 + 7 = 12’) suggests that <strong>the</strong>ir assertion will carry<br />

commitment to numbers. Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness of<br />

speakers to assert simple arithmetic sums seems to turn<br />

on <strong>the</strong>ir belief <strong>in</strong> some sort of generalisation (evidence for<br />

which is obta<strong>in</strong>ed by count<strong>in</strong>g), <strong>and</strong> is apparently<br />

<strong>in</strong>dependent of <strong>the</strong>ir belief <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence of arithmetical<br />

objects. So it is prima facie plausible that simple arithmetic<br />

sums may be paraphrased by sentences whose literal<br />

assertion would not carry commitment to arithmetical<br />

objects.<br />

2.<br />

This may sound familiar. There have been previous attempts<br />

to paraphrase (or o<strong>the</strong>rwise provide a reduction of)<br />

<strong>the</strong> sentences of pure arithmetic <strong>in</strong> terms of generalisations<br />

constructed us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> adjectival (or quantificational<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er) occurrences of number-words or numerals (for<br />

an overview, see (Rayo forthcom<strong>in</strong>g)). These have typically<br />

been undertaken <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of a defence of nom<strong>in</strong>alism<br />

or logicism (or both). The follow<strong>in</strong>g works are<br />

broadly <strong>in</strong> defense of an adjectival strategy: (Bostock<br />

1974); (Gottlieb 1980); (Hodes 1984); (Rayo 2002).<br />

A st<strong>and</strong>ard start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for such reductions is <strong>the</strong><br />

paraphras<strong>in</strong>g of arithmetic sums as generalizations<br />

constructed us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> material conditional. For present<br />

purposes, it is more plausible for c<strong>and</strong>idate paraphrases to<br />

<strong>in</strong>volve natural language conditionals. An <strong>in</strong>itial suggestion<br />

might be that (schematically)<br />

(4) m + n = p<br />

may be paraphrased as <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicative conditional<br />

(5) for any concept F, <strong>and</strong> any concept G, if <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are exactly m objects that fall under F, exactly n objects<br />

that fall under G, <strong>and</strong> no objects fall under both<br />

F <strong>and</strong> G, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re are exactly p objects which fall<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r under F or under G<br />

It is a good question whe<strong>the</strong>r natural language sentences<br />

<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicative conditional have <strong>the</strong> same truth<br />

conditions as parallel sentences constructed us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

material conditional. If <strong>the</strong>se particular <strong>in</strong>dicative conditionals<br />

do, <strong>the</strong>n that creates a potential problem for <strong>the</strong><br />

c<strong>and</strong>idate paraphrases: <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard distribution of truth<br />

values will be preserved only if <strong>the</strong>re are <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely many<br />

objects. For if <strong>the</strong>re are less than m objects, <strong>the</strong> paraphrase<br />

of m + n = p will be true even <strong>in</strong> a case where <strong>the</strong><br />

paraphrased utterance is st<strong>and</strong>ardly taken to be false.<br />

It is st<strong>and</strong>ardly compla<strong>in</strong>ed (for example <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

context of nom<strong>in</strong>alist treatments of arithmetic) that such a<br />

reduction would be <strong>the</strong>oretically flawed because, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

absence of fur<strong>the</strong>r assumptions, it would leave open <strong>the</strong><br />

epistemic possibility that <strong>the</strong>re is a non-st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

distribution of <strong>the</strong> truth values of arithmetic sentences.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong> truth of any particular arithmetical sentence<br />

would be cont<strong>in</strong>gent on <strong>the</strong>re be<strong>in</strong>g enough objects around<br />

(<strong>the</strong> only necessarily true sum would be ‘0 + 0 = 0’).<br />

A related problem for <strong>the</strong> proposed reduction is that<br />

<strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness of speakers to assert or deny arithmetic<br />

sums <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard distribution of truth values<br />

should not be – but plausibly is - <strong>in</strong>dependent of <strong>the</strong>ir belief<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itude of <strong>the</strong> world. Might <strong>the</strong>n (4) be better paraphrased<br />

as a counterfactual (or subjunctive) conditional? A<br />

good c<strong>and</strong>idate would be<br />

(6) for any concept F, <strong>and</strong> any concept G, if <strong>the</strong>re<br />

were exactly m objects that fell under F, exactly n<br />

objects that fell under G, <strong>and</strong> no objects fell under<br />

both F <strong>and</strong> G, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re would be exactly p objects<br />

which fell ei<strong>the</strong>r under F or under G<br />

This is an appeal<strong>in</strong>g paraphrase. On limited assumptions<br />

concern<strong>in</strong>g modality (firstly that each world accesses some<br />

larger world, <strong>and</strong> secondly that <strong>the</strong> modal logic is at least

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!