02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>the</strong>re is a tension between evaluat<strong>in</strong>g ¬Tr(‘φ’) <strong>and</strong> φ<br />

equally, <strong>and</strong> evaluat<strong>in</strong>g ¬Tr(‘φ’) <strong>and</strong> φ differently. The first<br />

tension <strong>in</strong>dicates that ¬Tr(‘φ’) is context-dependent.<br />

Concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> second tension we have two possible l<strong>in</strong>es<br />

of explanation available. We can ei<strong>the</strong>r aga<strong>in</strong> trust <strong>in</strong>to<br />

effects of a context-shift, but we can alternatively argue<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> rule (SoI).<br />

On a first assessment one might for economical<br />

reasons decide to make an effort to solve <strong>the</strong> problem by<br />

employ<strong>in</strong>g an explanation <strong>in</strong> terms of context-shift only. I<br />

shall simply call this <strong>the</strong> context-based approach <strong>in</strong> order<br />

to dist<strong>in</strong>guish it from <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r strategies. Generally, any<br />

context-based approach has to clarify what k<strong>in</strong>d of contextdependence<br />

is present <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>ned liar reason<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

It has to determ<strong>in</strong>e where a context-dependent element is<br />

hidden <strong>in</strong> ¬Tr(‘φ’).<br />

All context-based approaches agree that a certa<strong>in</strong><br />

change of context affects our <strong>in</strong>terpretation of <strong>the</strong> truth<br />

predicate Tr occurr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> φ. A very direct realization of this<br />

comes from (Burge 1979). He proposes to add an <strong>in</strong>dex i<br />

to each occurrence of Tr, i.e. “Tri”. This rem<strong>in</strong>ds very much<br />

of Tarski´s proposal, but Burge`s system has several<br />

advantages. Formulas, such as “Tri(‘Tri(‘P(c)’)’)” where<br />

“P(c)” represents “Snow is white”, that are mean<strong>in</strong>gless or<br />

ill-formed accord<strong>in</strong>g to Tarski´s account, become<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gful with<strong>in</strong> Burge´s system. Fur<strong>the</strong>r developments<br />

of Burge´s approach are (Koons 1992) <strong>and</strong> (Simmons<br />

1993).<br />

A metaphysically more sophisticated approach is<br />

posed by (Parsons 1974), (Barwise <strong>and</strong> Etchemendy<br />

1987) <strong>and</strong> (Glanzberg 2004). Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Parsons <strong>and</strong><br />

Glanzberg, a context-shift can lead to a shift from M to<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r L-structure M* which is regarded to be an<br />

expansion of M. They take propositions as truth-bearers,<br />

<strong>and</strong> def<strong>in</strong>e an expression relation between sentences <strong>and</strong><br />

propositions. The universe of discourse D of <strong>the</strong>ir model M<br />

is proposed to conta<strong>in</strong> all propositions that can be<br />

expressed by L M (<strong>in</strong> Glanzberg´s system, D actually<br />

conta<strong>in</strong>s all truth conditions that can constitute a<br />

proposition <strong>and</strong> that can be expressed by L M ). The<br />

universe can exp<strong>and</strong> as context shifts. In <strong>the</strong> first place,<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore, quantifiers represent <strong>the</strong> context-dependent<br />

element <strong>in</strong> (Glanzbergs <strong>and</strong> Parsons versions of) <strong>the</strong><br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ned liar sentence. But as Glanzberg <strong>and</strong> Parsons<br />

note, it is <strong>the</strong>n only a def<strong>in</strong>itional matter to work with a<br />

context-dependent truth predicate, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> fact both end up<br />

with work<strong>in</strong>g with a context-dependent truth predicate.<br />

(Barwise <strong>and</strong> Etchemendy 1987) give a very similar<br />

account.<br />

Context-based approaches employ an analysis that<br />

<strong>in</strong>evitably gives rise to a certa<strong>in</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d of hierarchy of truth<br />

predicates. This is obvious for proposals which attach an<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex belong<strong>in</strong>g to a partially ordered set to all<br />

occurrences of “Tr”. Approaches that appeal to an<br />

expansion M* of M with a more comprehensive doma<strong>in</strong> D*<br />

lead to a hierarchical view as well. The language L M*<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpreted by M* is used to express a true statement<br />

about φ' (<strong>the</strong> “ ' ” <strong>in</strong>dicates that φ' is actually a translation of<br />

<strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al φ belong<strong>in</strong>g to L M <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> language L M* ): M* ├<br />

Tr*(‘φ'’), <strong>and</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>rmore M* ├ ¬Tr(‘φ'’), where <strong>the</strong><br />

Context-Based Approaches to <strong>the</strong> Streng<strong>the</strong>ned Liar Problem — Christ<strong>in</strong>e Schurz<br />

predicate Tr represents “truth <strong>in</strong> L M ” <strong>and</strong> Tr* represents<br />

“truth <strong>in</strong> L M* ”. A new streng<strong>the</strong>ned liar sentence φ* of <strong>the</strong><br />

form ¬Tr*(l) such that l = ‘¬Tr*(l)’ can be formed that gives<br />

rise to ano<strong>the</strong>r context-shift that is associated with ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

model M** to reason about φ*. M** <strong>in</strong> turn has its own<br />

truth-predicate Tr** <strong>and</strong> so on <strong>and</strong> so forth.<br />

Of course <strong>the</strong> hierarchies advanced by contextbased<br />

approaches differ from Tarski´s hierarchies of truthpredicates<br />

<strong>in</strong> several respects. First, as I have already<br />

mentioned, this approach features some advantages,<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce several cases of formulas that correspond to<br />

ord<strong>in</strong>ary <strong>and</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gful sentences <strong>in</strong> English, but that<br />

become pathological <strong>in</strong> Tarski´s system, are evaluated as<br />

our <strong>in</strong>tuitions would suggest it. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong>se<br />

alternative hierarchies are considered to model natural<br />

language as closely as this can possibly be done, or even<br />

to represent an <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic feature of natural language. The<br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ned liar problem does not show that <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

of truth <strong>in</strong> natural language is <strong>in</strong>consistent, but that <strong>the</strong><br />

predicate “is true” is context-dependent.<br />

Still it is prima facie undesired that <strong>the</strong> concept of<br />

truth is context-dependent. So context-based approaches<br />

have to give a motivation for this context-dependency. A<br />

very essential question is, what k<strong>in</strong>d of context-shift<br />

happens to effect a shift <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> extension of Tr <strong>and</strong> how it<br />

does this. Earlier proponents of context-based approaches<br />

do not employ any rigid formal concept of a context.<br />

Therefore <strong>the</strong>y only give rough <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formal explanations<br />

for this problem, if at all. Sometimes <strong>the</strong> presence of <strong>the</strong><br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ned liar problem is taken to provide enough<br />

evidence to prove a context-shift. In contrast, (Glanzberg<br />

2004) gives a rigid proof of how a context-shift leads to a<br />

shift from M to M*, which is based on precise notions of a<br />

context, a proposition <strong>and</strong> a truth predicate.<br />

An additional problem which I th<strong>in</strong>k deserves<br />

attention apart from any profound explanation concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> previous question is that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> languages proposed<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no way to reflect over all contexts. No formula can<br />

be used to represent an ultimate or universal perspective.<br />

Proponents of a contextual analysis have to clarify why this<br />

is so, <strong>and</strong> why our naive view that we can reflect over<br />

absolutely everyth<strong>in</strong>g is wrong.<br />

Apart from <strong>the</strong>se two problems a context-based<br />

approach also has to motivate why it fares better than<br />

alternative approaches to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>ned liar<br />

problem. Given all <strong>the</strong> difficulties related with a hierarchical<br />

account I have just outl<strong>in</strong>ed, it could e.g. be that contrary<br />

to our first assessment an alternative approach that relies<br />

<strong>in</strong> addition on restrict<strong>in</strong>g (SoI) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> end provides a better<br />

trade-off than a purely context-based approach. It has<br />

sometimes been argued aga<strong>in</strong>st restrict<strong>in</strong>g (SoI) that this<br />

l<strong>in</strong>e of solution was ad-hoc <strong>and</strong> unmotivated. For <strong>the</strong> most<br />

part this po<strong>in</strong>t applies to approaches put forward so far<br />

(e.g. (Skyrms 1970)), s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y are not very elaborated<br />

concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir applicability to natural language (besides,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y do not <strong>in</strong>voke any contextual considerations, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>refore do not expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first problem from which <strong>the</strong><br />

streng<strong>the</strong>ned liar problem arises). Therefore it could be<br />

<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to search for o<strong>the</strong>r k<strong>in</strong>ds of contextual<br />

approaches <strong>and</strong> turn our attention to (SoI).<br />

311

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!