02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Four-Color Theorem, Testimony <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> A Priori<br />

Kai-Yee Wong, Hong Kong, Ch<strong>in</strong>a<br />

1. Computer proof as experiment<br />

The computer played an essential role <strong>in</strong> provid<strong>in</strong>g a key<br />

lemma, which requires certa<strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>atorial checks too<br />

long to do by h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> proof given by Kenneth Appel<br />

<strong>and</strong> Wolfgang Hanken of <strong>the</strong> Four-Color Theorem (4CT).<br />

The proof of <strong>the</strong> 4CT has generated a flurry of philosophical<br />

discussions about its significance. Some of <strong>the</strong>m focused<br />

on <strong>the</strong> arguments put forth by Thomas Tymoczko<br />

1979. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Tymoczko, <strong>the</strong> argument for <strong>the</strong> 4CT is<br />

like ‘an argument <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical physics where a long argument<br />

can suggest a key experiment which is carried out<br />

<strong>and</strong> used to complete <strong>the</strong> argument’ (Tymoczko 1979: 78)<br />

because <strong>the</strong>re is an unavoidable reliance on computers to<br />

produce <strong>the</strong> proof of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orem. S<strong>in</strong>ce belief <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> reliability<br />

of computers ultimately rests on empirical considerations,<br />

<strong>the</strong> proof establishes <strong>the</strong> 4CT on grounds that<br />

are <strong>in</strong> part empirical. So <strong>the</strong> 4CT, Tymoczko concludes, is<br />

a substantial piece of knowledge which can be known only<br />

a posteriori. Almost three decades on, <strong>the</strong> issues raised by<br />

Tymoczko’s paper are still of great <strong>in</strong>terest to many. (For a<br />

recent discussion see, see Arkoudas <strong>and</strong> Br<strong>in</strong>gsjord 2007.<br />

See also Brown 1999, Burge 1998, Coady 1992: ch. 14.)<br />

In this paper I shall exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> central thread <strong>in</strong> Tymoczko’s<br />

reason<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Michael Detlefsen <strong>and</strong> Mark Luker’s<br />

(1980) contention that it <strong>in</strong> fact leads, rightly, to <strong>the</strong> much<br />

more drastic conclusion that ma<strong>the</strong>matical proof is typically<br />

empirical.<br />

Tymoczko argues that <strong>the</strong> appeal to computers, <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> case of <strong>the</strong> 4CT, <strong>in</strong>volves a claim of this k<strong>in</strong>d:<br />

(1) If computer C runn<strong>in</strong>g program P produces result<br />

R, <strong>the</strong>n ma<strong>the</strong>matical statement M is true.<br />

The truth of (1) turns on <strong>the</strong> reliability of C <strong>and</strong> P, which <strong>in</strong><br />

turn <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> claim that<br />

(2) C does what it is supposed to do, namely, to<br />

correctly execute P.<br />

Evidently (2) may turn out true or false, depend<strong>in</strong>g on a<br />

complex set of empirical factors <strong>and</strong> thus its truth is ‘ultimately<br />

a matter for eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> physics to assess’<br />

(Tymoczko 1979: 74). Ma<strong>the</strong>matical knowledge obta<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

by computer proof is <strong>the</strong>refore grounded on a ‘wellconceived<br />

computer experiment’. So, Tymoczko concludes,<br />

accept<strong>in</strong>g computer-assisted proof means giv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

up <strong>the</strong> traditional notion of ma<strong>the</strong>matical proof as someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

surveyable, non-empirical <strong>and</strong> a priori.<br />

2. Proof, archives, <strong>and</strong> testimony<br />

Express<strong>in</strong>g this argument <strong>in</strong> terms of testimony can help<br />

us articulate a problem for Tymoczko. What he argues for<br />

is that s<strong>in</strong>ce testimony is empirical <strong>in</strong> character <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

proof of <strong>the</strong> 4CT is based partly on <strong>the</strong> testimony of a<br />

computer, accept<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> 4CT as a <strong>the</strong>orem requires<br />

chang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> concept of proof.<br />

Indeed, it seems arguable that testimony has a<br />

significant role <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> transmission of ma<strong>the</strong>matical<br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> this <strong>in</strong> turn may have <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g bear<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on <strong>the</strong> notion of proof. Ma<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>in</strong>vestigation, of<br />

course, builds on past results. Now suppose Kodel, a<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matician, has produced with great care a proof with<br />

gaps filled by a set of established, ‘archived’ results. It is<br />

implausible to th<strong>in</strong>k that Kodel’s proof <strong>the</strong>refore fails to be<br />

a proof <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> proper sense, o<strong>the</strong>rwise much of<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matics as we know it would go down <strong>the</strong> dra<strong>in</strong><br />

because ma<strong>the</strong>matical <strong>in</strong>vestigation has always <strong>in</strong>volved<br />

appeals to, so to speak, testimony of archived results.<br />

Reliance on such testimony is part <strong>and</strong> parcel of a<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matician’s work. Thus, <strong>in</strong> a crucial respect, Kodel’s<br />

proof, or for that matter, much of traditional ma<strong>the</strong>matical<br />

<strong>in</strong>vestigation is relevantly similar to <strong>the</strong> proof of <strong>the</strong> 4CT <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir reliance on testimony. If we adopt Tymoczko’s view,<br />

we must say that <strong>the</strong> use of testimony <strong>in</strong>jected <strong>in</strong>to Kodel’s<br />

proof empirical <strong>in</strong>gredients <strong>and</strong> rendered <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orem<br />

proved a piece of a posteriori knowledge, just as <strong>the</strong> 4CT<br />

is. Notice whe<strong>the</strong>r or not Kodel can survey <strong>the</strong> archived<br />

proofs has no bear<strong>in</strong>g on this po<strong>in</strong>t. To see this, we can<br />

imag<strong>in</strong>e that ano<strong>the</strong>r ma<strong>the</strong>matician, Podel, produced a<br />

proof with gaps filled by a vast set of archived results.<br />

Survey<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> enormously complex <strong>and</strong> numerous proofs<br />

for <strong>the</strong>se results is such a mammoth task that no<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matician can f<strong>in</strong>ish. (If this sounds far-fetched,<br />

consider <strong>the</strong> now accepted proof of <strong>the</strong> classification of all<br />

simple f<strong>in</strong>ite groups. The proof, carried out over many<br />

years by a large number of ma<strong>the</strong>maticians, spans across<br />

about 15,000 pages on journals. This example is from<br />

Brown (1999), p. 158). The fact that <strong>the</strong>se proofs have<br />

been surveyed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> past will not change <strong>the</strong> situation. For<br />

without a first-h<strong>and</strong> survey of each proof, Podel must rely<br />

on empirical evidence that <strong>the</strong> archives are a reliable<br />

source of ma<strong>the</strong>matical results. It is arbitrary to claim that<br />

Kodel’s <strong>the</strong>orem does not rely on any empirical evidence<br />

because his proof is not as extensive as Podel’s <strong>in</strong> its<br />

appeal to <strong>the</strong> archives.<br />

If so, one should f<strong>in</strong>d puzzl<strong>in</strong>g if not <strong>in</strong>consistent<br />

Tymoczko’s claim that <strong>the</strong> appeal to computers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 4CT<br />

forces a change of <strong>the</strong> traditional concept of proof. For if<br />

this claim is to be true, it must be <strong>the</strong> case that<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matical proof had not come to <strong>in</strong>clude empirical<br />

elements before <strong>the</strong> proof of <strong>the</strong> 4CT. But by d<strong>in</strong>t of<br />

reason<strong>in</strong>g similar to Tymoczko’s own, as shown by <strong>the</strong><br />

case of Kodel <strong>and</strong> Podel, it should be held, albeit <strong>in</strong> my<br />

view implausibly, that traditional ma<strong>the</strong>matics is mostly<br />

empirical.<br />

Yet one may th<strong>in</strong>k that such a conclusion is not<br />

implausible. As a matter of fact, some have argued that<br />

much of traditional ma<strong>the</strong>matics is partially empirical.<br />

Detlefsen <strong>and</strong> Luker (1980) argue that if one follows <strong>the</strong><br />

logic of Tymoczko’s reason<strong>in</strong>g where it leads, one is forced<br />

to see empirical <strong>in</strong>gredients <strong>in</strong> proofs that are generally<br />

held to be paradigms of a priori ma<strong>the</strong>matical arguments,<br />

such as <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g one attributed to <strong>the</strong> young Gauss.<br />

Gauss proved that <strong>the</strong> sum of <strong>the</strong> first one hundred<br />

positive numbers was 5,050 <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g way: write<br />

down <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g pairs: , , …, ,<br />

observe that <strong>the</strong> numbers of each pair toge<strong>the</strong>r make 101<br />

<strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>re are 50 pairs, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n conclude that <strong>the</strong><br />

sum of <strong>the</strong> first one hundred numbers is 5,050. Accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to Detlefsen <strong>and</strong> Luker, <strong>the</strong> episode of calculation by which<br />

we determ<strong>in</strong>ate that 101 multiplied by 50 is 5,050 is<br />

needed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> ‘observation’ to <strong>the</strong><br />

‘conclusion’. Among <strong>the</strong> assumptions, <strong>the</strong>y add, required<br />

399

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!