02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

D<strong>in</strong>g-Ontology of Aristotle vs. Sachverhalt-Ontology of<br />

Wittgenste<strong>in</strong><br />

Serguei L. Katrechko, Moscow, Russia<br />

In <strong>the</strong> history of philosophy, we can dist<strong>in</strong>guish three<br />

possible types of ontology 1 . The first claims that <strong>the</strong> world<br />

‘is made up’ of th<strong>in</strong>gs that are considered its <strong>in</strong>itial<br />

elements. In <strong>the</strong> Antiquity, <strong>the</strong> ontology of th<strong>in</strong>gs tender<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to nom<strong>in</strong>alism was presented by Aristotle <strong>and</strong> Democritus,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir concepts, despite <strong>the</strong> differences, belong to <strong>the</strong><br />

same type of ontology. They differ only on a scale of<br />

‘th<strong>in</strong>g-ism’, <strong>the</strong> former postulat<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> world consists of<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>the</strong> latter consider<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> world is built up of<br />

atomic ‘bricks’, or particles, regarded as micro–th<strong>in</strong>gs, that,<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir term, make up ord<strong>in</strong>ary th<strong>in</strong>gs that we are used to.<br />

And it is <strong>the</strong> ontology of th<strong>in</strong>gs that has been an<br />

overwhelm<strong>in</strong>g ontology of contemporary natural science.<br />

The second <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> third types of ontology are<br />

based on predicate <strong>in</strong>terpretation of be<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> postulate a<br />

non-object character of <strong>the</strong> world. If we take <strong>the</strong> classical<br />

approach to structure a sentence (resp. <strong>the</strong> world) as 'S is<br />

P’ <strong>the</strong> ontology of th<strong>in</strong>gs is accented on ’S is— ’, with ‘S is’<br />

represent<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>separably l<strong>in</strong>ked complex, <strong>and</strong> S — <strong>the</strong><br />

essence of <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g which acts as a substance for<br />

predicates of <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g (resp. grammatically S acts as <strong>the</strong><br />

subject of <strong>the</strong> sentence). Predicate ontology is <strong>the</strong> one of<br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘— is Pх’ type where ‘th<strong>in</strong>gs’ (resp. subjects of <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence) become secondary formations, <strong>and</strong> are<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>ed not by <strong>the</strong> essence but by <strong>the</strong>ir predicates.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, esse is be<strong>in</strong>g related here not with <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

but with <strong>the</strong> prior–predicate ‘is’ (resp. l<strong>in</strong>k–verb of <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence), <strong>and</strong> produces as transcendental condition for<br />

<strong>the</strong> rest ‘real’ predicates of <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g (P1, P2, P3…).<br />

We can also mark out two subtypes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> predicate<br />

ontology. The first one presents be<strong>in</strong>g as property (resp.<br />

unary P 1<br />

n predicate), with property <strong>in</strong>terpreted as ‘— is P 1<br />

n’<br />

<strong>in</strong>separably l<strong>in</strong>ked predicative complex. It is <strong>the</strong> property of<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs that is considered prior <strong>in</strong> ontology while th<strong>in</strong>gs,<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g secondary, act as ‘<strong>in</strong>tersections’ of properties<br />

(bundle <strong>the</strong>ory of substance). For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>the</strong> table is<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g that is made of wood, right–angled, yellow, <strong>and</strong><br />

used for writ<strong>in</strong>g. Here, someth<strong>in</strong>g is predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed by its<br />

properties (as unary predicates). Plato’s ontology has<br />

been <strong>the</strong> first <strong>and</strong> form<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory of <strong>the</strong> type so, this type of<br />

ontology can be named Platonic ontology. It’s possible to<br />

demonstrate that such <strong>in</strong>terpretation of Plato’s idealism<br />

does not sound like idealism at all. Priority of Plato’s ‘world<br />

of ideas’ might be understood as a mere acceptance of<br />

priority of properties (predicative complex ’is P 1<br />

n’) <strong>in</strong><br />

respect of th<strong>in</strong>g (S–subject). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, similar concepts<br />

are more realistic as compared to both, Aristotelian<br />

ontology <strong>and</strong> natural ontology of contemporary natural<br />

science presum<strong>in</strong>g virtual existence of matter (as<br />

universal), for we experience not ‘disguised’ (latent)<br />

Aristotelian essence <strong>and</strong> not hypo<strong>the</strong>tic matter postulated<br />

by up-to-date physics (e.g. dark matter <strong>in</strong> astronomy) but<br />

1 The term ‘ontology’ will be used here <strong>in</strong> two related but a bit different mean<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

The <strong>in</strong>itial mean<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> word is concerned with <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e (teach<strong>in</strong>g)<br />

of "be<strong>in</strong>g qua be<strong>in</strong>g" (Aristotle, metaphysica generalis). The second one<br />

studies how <strong>the</strong> universe is made up, i.e. what ontological commitments we<br />

accept (metaphysica specialis). Fur<strong>the</strong>r on, we’ll speak of concrete ontology<br />

(<strong>the</strong> second mean<strong>in</strong>g) which depends on <strong>the</strong> general underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g of existence.<br />

real properties of objects that we can discover objectively,<br />

through perception or by means of <strong>in</strong>struments.<br />

It’s worth not<strong>in</strong>g, that Aristotelian <strong>and</strong> Platonic<br />

ontology do not reject but, ra<strong>the</strong>r, enrich each o<strong>the</strong>r. These<br />

are two different approaches to <strong>the</strong> world def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g its<br />

diverse sections, <strong>and</strong> each of two has <strong>the</strong> right to be<br />

(similar to corpuscular wave dualism <strong>in</strong> physics). They<br />

produce two necessary (transcendental) conditions of<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g of objects. The first one postulates <strong>the</strong> presence of<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle self-identical essence as an <strong>in</strong>dispensable ‘sublayer’<br />

(sub–stance) for property of th<strong>in</strong>g, while <strong>the</strong> second one<br />

dictates <strong>the</strong> necessity ‘to partake’ th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> world of<br />

ideas which term<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>the</strong> possibility to take <strong>in</strong>to<br />

possession this or that set of properties.<br />

Explication of <strong>the</strong> second predicate ontology was<br />

made much later on. It <strong>in</strong>terprets be<strong>in</strong>g as relation (n–ary<br />

predicate P k<br />

n.), with Tractatus be<strong>in</strong>g one of its variations<br />

pronounc<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> world is <strong>the</strong> totality of facts, not of<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs (prop. 1.1). Here, facts act as someth<strong>in</strong>g different<br />

from th<strong>in</strong>gs, as a sort of relation between th<strong>in</strong>gs or<br />

‘comb<strong>in</strong>ations of th<strong>in</strong>gs’ (prop. 2.01). Hence, under<br />

Tractatus, it is relation that is believed to be prior while<br />

object is def<strong>in</strong>ed through a set of relations it could become<br />

a constituent part of, <strong>and</strong>, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong><br />

possibility of that must be already written <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> object<br />

itself (prop. 2.011–2.0121).<br />

This proposition differs from Aristotelian ontology<br />

consider<strong>in</strong>g essence prior to relation that may be added to<br />

it as r<strong>and</strong>om (accidental) characteristic: ‘that which is per<br />

se, i.e. substance, is prior <strong>in</strong> nature to <strong>the</strong> relative for <strong>the</strong><br />

latter is like an off-shoot <strong>and</strong> accident of be<strong>in</strong>g’ (Aristotle,<br />

Nicomachean Ethics, 1096а20; Boethius, On <strong>the</strong> Tr<strong>in</strong>ity,<br />

§ 5). Challeng<strong>in</strong>g such an underestimation of ‘relation’<br />

category Plato, <strong>in</strong> anticipation to Tractatus speculations,<br />

could have argued that ‘anyth<strong>in</strong>g which possesses any<br />

sort of power to affect ano<strong>the</strong>r, or to be affected by<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r… had real existence’ (Plato, Sophist, 247e), i.e.<br />

really exists only that which is able to <strong>in</strong>teract. Then, one<br />

more transcendental condition is be<strong>in</strong>g revealed, that is<br />

relations (<strong>in</strong>teractions) deprived of which not a th<strong>in</strong>g could<br />

exist (resp. esse acts here as grounds for any ‘real’<br />

relations) 2 . We can register th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>to ontology status of<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g provided that all three transcendental condition are<br />

observed.<br />

Thus, we can separate three types of ontology: <strong>the</strong><br />

ontology of th<strong>in</strong>gs, attributes <strong>and</strong> relations. Each of <strong>the</strong>m is<br />

correlated with a particular type of language. In <strong>the</strong><br />

ontology of th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong> key structure belongs to <strong>the</strong> noun.<br />

Esse <strong>in</strong>terpreted as property, <strong>the</strong> key position goes to <strong>the</strong><br />

adjective. With esse conceived as relations, separate<br />

words (nours, verbs or adjective) give way to <strong>the</strong> whole<br />

sentence structure, express<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> facts of relationship<br />

between objects. For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>the</strong> sentence ‘The stone is<br />

fall<strong>in</strong>g’ which purportedly postulates existence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world<br />

of Aristotelian ‘<strong>in</strong>itial entities’ (here: stones) able to act, will<br />

2 To put it more precisely, had an object ever existed, s<strong>in</strong>ce it never becomes<br />

a constituent part of any relation, we couldn’t have learnt about it s<strong>in</strong>ce learn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

is also a relation between an object <strong>and</strong> a subject.<br />

169

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!