25.06.2013 Views

statistique, théorie et gestion de portefeuille - Docs at ISFA

statistique, théorie et gestion de portefeuille - Docs at ISFA

statistique, théorie et gestion de portefeuille - Docs at ISFA

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

164 6. Comportements mimétiques <strong>et</strong> antagonistes : bulles hyperboliques, krachs <strong>et</strong> chaos<br />

Q UANTITATIVE F INANCE Imit<strong>at</strong>ion and contrarian behaviour: hyperbolic bubbles, crashes and chaos<br />

value investors (I<strong>de</strong> and Sorn<strong>et</strong>te 2001, Sorn<strong>et</strong>te and I<strong>de</strong> 2001).<br />

We build on this insight and construct a very simple mo<strong>de</strong>l<br />

of price dynamics, which puts emphasis on the fundamental<br />

nonlinear behaviour of both classes of agents.<br />

These well-known principles gener<strong>at</strong>e different kinds of<br />

risks b<strong>et</strong>ween which agents choose by arbitrage. The former<br />

is a comp<strong>et</strong>ing risk (Keynes 1936, Orléan 1989) which leads<br />

agents to imit<strong>at</strong>e the collective point of view since the mark<strong>et</strong><br />

price inclu<strong>de</strong>s it. Thus, it is assumed th<strong>at</strong> Keynes’ animal<br />

spirits may exist. More simply, there is the risk of mistaken<br />

expect<strong>at</strong>ion: agents believe in a price different from the mark<strong>et</strong><br />

price. Keynes uses his famous beauty contest as a parable<br />

for stock mark<strong>et</strong>s. In or<strong>de</strong>r to predict the winner of a beauty<br />

contest, objective beauty is not very important, but knowledge<br />

or prediction of others’ prediction of beauty is. In Keynes’<br />

view, the optimal str<strong>at</strong>egy is not to pick those faces the player<br />

thinks the pr<strong>et</strong>tiest, but those the other players are likely to<br />

think the average opinion will be, or those the other players<br />

will think the others will think the average opinion will be, or<br />

even further along this iter<strong>at</strong>ive loop.<br />

On the other hand, in the l<strong>at</strong>ter case, the emerging<br />

price is not necessarily in harmony with economic reality<br />

and fundamental value. Self-referred <strong>de</strong>cisions and selfvalid<strong>at</strong>ion<br />

phenomena can then in<strong>de</strong>ed lead to specul<strong>at</strong>ive<br />

bubbles or sunspots (i.e. external random events) (Azariadis<br />

1981, Azariadis and Guesnerie 1982, Blanchard and W<strong>at</strong>son<br />

1982, Jevons 1871, Kreps 1977). Thus, the l<strong>at</strong>ter risk is<br />

the result of precaution. It addresses the fitting of mark<strong>et</strong><br />

price to fundamental value and, by extension, collapse of the<br />

specul<strong>at</strong>ive bubble.<br />

Both <strong>at</strong>titu<strong>de</strong>s are likely to be important and are integr<strong>at</strong>ed<br />

in <strong>de</strong>cision rules. Agents realize an arbitrage b<strong>et</strong>ween the two<br />

kinds of risk we have <strong>de</strong>scribed. Th<strong>at</strong> is why they have both a<br />

mim<strong>et</strong>ic behaviour and an antagonistic one: they either follow<br />

the collective point of view or they have reversed expect<strong>at</strong>ions.<br />

We are now going to put these assumptions into the<br />

simplest possible m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical form. We assume th<strong>at</strong>, <strong>at</strong><br />

any given time t, the popul<strong>at</strong>ion is divi<strong>de</strong>d into two parts.<br />

Agents are explicitly differenti<strong>at</strong>ed as being bullish or bearish<br />

in proportions pt and qt = 1 − pt respectively. The first ones<br />

expect an increase of the price, while the bearish ones expect<br />

a <strong>de</strong>crease. The agents then form their opinion for time t +1<br />

by sampling the expect<strong>at</strong>ions of m other agents <strong>at</strong> time t, and<br />

modifying their own expect<strong>at</strong>ions accordingly. The number m<br />

of agents polled by a given agent to form her opinion <strong>at</strong> time<br />

t + 1 is the first important param<strong>et</strong>er in our mo<strong>de</strong>l.<br />

We then introduce threshold <strong>de</strong>nsities ρhb and ρhh. We<br />

assume 0 ρhb ρhh 1. A bullish agent will change<br />

opinion if <strong>at</strong> least one of the following propositions is true.<br />

(1) At least m · ρhb among the m agents inspected are bearish.<br />

(2) At least m · ρhh among the m agents inspected are bullish.<br />

The first case corresponds to ‘following the crowd’, while<br />

the second case corresponds to the ‘antagonistic behaviour’.<br />

The quantity ρhb is thus the threshold for a bullish agent<br />

(‘haussier’) to become bearish (‘baissier’) for mim<strong>et</strong>ic reasons,<br />

and similarly, ρhh is the threshold for a bullish agent to<br />

become bearish because there are ‘too many’ bullish agents.<br />

One reason for this behaviour is, as we said, th<strong>at</strong> the <strong>de</strong>vi<strong>at</strong>ion<br />

of the mark<strong>et</strong> price from the fundamental value is felt to be<br />

unsustainable. Another reason is th<strong>at</strong> if many managers tell<br />

you th<strong>at</strong> they are bullish, it is probable th<strong>at</strong> they have large<br />

‘long’ positions in the mark<strong>et</strong>: they therefore tell you to buy,<br />

hoping to be able to unfold in part their position in favourable<br />

conditions with a good profit.<br />

The <strong>de</strong>vi<strong>at</strong>ion of the threshold ρhb above the symm<strong>et</strong>ric<br />

value 1/2 is a measure of the ‘stubbornness’ (or ‘buy-and-hold’<br />

ten<strong>de</strong>ncy) of the agent to keep her position. For ρhb = 1/2,<br />

the agent strictly endorses without <strong>de</strong>lay the opinion of the<br />

majority and believes in any weak trend. This corresponds to a<br />

reversible dynamics. A value ρhb > 1/2 expresses a ten<strong>de</strong>ncy<br />

towards conserv<strong>at</strong>ism: a large ρhb means th<strong>at</strong> the agent will<br />

rarely change opinion. She is risk-adverse and would like to<br />

see an almost unanimity appearing before changing her mind.<br />

Her future behaviour has thus a strong memory of her past<br />

position. ρhb − 1/2 can be called the bullish ‘buy-and-hold’<br />

in<strong>de</strong>x.<br />

The <strong>de</strong>vi<strong>at</strong>ion of the threshold ρhh below 1 quantifies the<br />

strength of disbelief of the agent in the sustainability of a<br />

specul<strong>at</strong>ive trend. For ρhh = 1, she always follows the crowd<br />

and is never contrarian. For ρhh close to 1/2, she has little faith<br />

in trend-following str<strong>at</strong>egies and is closer to a fundamentalist,<br />

expecting the price to revert rapidly to its fundamental value.<br />

1 − ρhh can be called the bullish reversal in<strong>de</strong>x.<br />

Putting the above rules into m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical equ<strong>at</strong>ions we<br />

see th<strong>at</strong> the probability P for an agent who is bullish <strong>at</strong> time t<br />

to change his opinion <strong>at</strong> time t + 1 is:<br />

P = prob({x mρhh}), (1)<br />

where x is the number of bullish agents found in the sample of<br />

m agents.<br />

In an entirely similar way, we introduce thresholds ρbh,<br />

and ρbb. The thresholds ρbh and ρbb have compl<strong>et</strong>ely<br />

symm<strong>et</strong>ric roles when the agent is initially bearish. ρbh − 1/2<br />

can be called the bearish ‘buy-and-hold’ in<strong>de</strong>x. 1 − ρbb can<br />

be called the bearish reversal in<strong>de</strong>x. The probability Q for a<br />

bearish agent <strong>at</strong> time t to become bullish <strong>at</strong> time t + 1 is:<br />

Q = prob({x mρbb}).<br />

We can combine these two rules into a dynamical law<br />

governing the time evolution of the popul<strong>at</strong>ions. Denoting pt<br />

the proportion of bullish agents in the popul<strong>at</strong>ion <strong>at</strong> time t,we<br />

can find the new proportion, pt+1, <strong>at</strong> time t + 1, by taking into<br />

account those agents which have changed opinion according to<br />

the d<strong>et</strong>erministic law given above. To simplify not<strong>at</strong>ion, we l<strong>et</strong><br />

pt+1 = p ′ and pt = p. Then, the above st<strong>at</strong>ements are easily<br />

used to express p ′ in terms of p, by using the probability of<br />

finding j bullish people among m (Corcos 1993):<br />

p ′ = p − p<br />

<br />

<br />

m<br />

p<br />

j<br />

m−j (1 − p) j<br />

+ (1 − p)<br />

jm·ρhb<br />

or j

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!