28.02.2015 Views

CORRUPTION Syndromes of Corruption

CORRUPTION Syndromes of Corruption

CORRUPTION Syndromes of Corruption

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

From analysis to reform 217<br />

democracies – attributes that, as noted, are more the outcomes than the<br />

causes <strong>of</strong> long-term development. But a time will come when a country<br />

needs to adapt to new challenges and open up to more diverse political<br />

expectations – including those born <strong>of</strong> its own successes. At that point<br />

tight elite networks may prove too rigid.<br />

In the end both reform and systemic adaptation require vigorous<br />

political contention among groups strong enough to demand that others<br />

respect their interests, rights, and property – not just stability or administrative<br />

improvements. Too <strong>of</strong>ten we think <strong>of</strong> reform as a process <strong>of</strong><br />

asking people to back <strong>of</strong>f from their own interests and ‘‘be good,’’ or <strong>of</strong><br />

trying to restrain political influence to as narrow a range <strong>of</strong> functions as<br />

possible. But in fact reform will be most sustainable and effective when<br />

driven by self-interest, and when distinctions between state and society,<br />

public and private, are not just abstractions but accepted boundaries<br />

drawn, redrawn, and defended by actively contending groups.<br />

At several points I have noted Rustow’s (1970) argument that the forces<br />

sustaining democracy where it is strong are not necessarily the ones that<br />

brought it into being. Affluence, literacy, a middle class, a free press and<br />

independent judiciary, and a strong civil society (to name but a few such<br />

elements) undoubtedly contribute to the vitality <strong>of</strong> democracy systems.<br />

But where did those elements come from, and how did democratic values<br />

take root? For Rustow, the answers lie in continuing political contention<br />

among groups embodying real social interests, over issues that are important<br />

to them (Rustow, 1970: 352). Democracy and good government are<br />

not necessarily the point <strong>of</strong> such struggles; more <strong>of</strong>ten they revolve around<br />

much more specific and immediate issues, with views on the ways government<br />

ought to operate serving more as weapons in the struggle than as<br />

ultimate goals (Rustow, 1970: 353). Much the same can be said with<br />

respect to controlling corruption: many <strong>of</strong> today’s low-corruption societies<br />

brought the problem under control in the course <strong>of</strong> fighting over other<br />

issues. The matter at hand might have been land, taxes, religion, or<br />

language, but the deeper issue was who had power, how they got it, and<br />

what could and could not be done with it. The inconclusive nature <strong>of</strong> those<br />

conflicts, too, was essential to their significance: no group got all it wanted,<br />

but the resulting settlements defined acceptable domains <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />

power and private interest, and set workable limits as to how wealth and<br />

power could be sought and used. Such settlements are rarely precise and<br />

never permanent: boundaries between public and private dealings, for<br />

example, are <strong>of</strong>ten redrawn. But they survive and adapt not because they<br />

are ‘‘good ideas’’ but because people have a stake in them.<br />

Magna Carta, for example, was not a ringing declaration <strong>of</strong> the rights <strong>of</strong><br />

humanity or a scheme for good government, but rather a set <strong>of</strong> limits laid

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!