03.06.2013 Views

JUDAICA - Wisdom In Torah

JUDAICA - Wisdom In Torah

JUDAICA - Wisdom In Torah

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

drinking, no bathing, no anointing, no sexual intercourse; but<br />

the righteous sit with crowns upon their heads and enjoy the<br />

splendor of the Shekhinah” in the following manner: “‘crowns<br />

upon their heads’ means the survival of the soul by virtue of<br />

the survival of knowledge, the two being one and the same<br />

thing; ‘enjoying the splendor of the Shekhinah’ means taking<br />

delight in the intellection of the Creator, even as the holy<br />

ḥayyot and the other angelic orders delight in their comprehension<br />

of His existence.” Maimonides, it should be noted,<br />

distinguished between the World-to-Come, which is an incorporeal<br />

state, and Paradise, which is a place here on earth.<br />

The treatise known as Perakim be-Haẓlaḥah (“Chapters on<br />

Beatitude”) has been wrongly ascribed to Maimonides, but it<br />

expresses views similar to his. Affirming that felicity is possible<br />

in this world and the next, the treatise distinguishes between<br />

the ecstatic experience of prophecy and the ultimate felicity<br />

of the soul’s union with God in the next world. Prophecy is<br />

described as the stage of human perfection at which the rational<br />

soul, like a polished mirror, reflects the light of the supernal<br />

world. At this stage one is happy, though one’s joy is<br />

tempered with the fear of God. Prophecy can be reached only<br />

after a search for wisdom and after subjecting the senses to a<br />

rigorous discipline. Imagination functions at this level under<br />

the complete control of the intellect (cf. Maimonides’ letter<br />

in Koveẓ Teshuvot ha-Rambam, 2:39b, where the same motif<br />

is quoted in the name of Abraham Ibn Ezra’s commentary<br />

on Ex. 23:20). The ultimate felicity, on the other hand, is the<br />

reward which all righteous may expect in the next world according<br />

to the measure of their worthiness. The author adds<br />

that this view of the afterlife is in agreement with the views<br />

of the philosophers, whereby he seems to refer to al-Farabi<br />

(in his earlier works) and Avicenna. The author assures his<br />

reader that every man can rise to a rank close to Moses’ (for<br />

which there is a parallel in Guide, 3:51), and, echoing neoplatonic<br />

traditions, he states that ultimate felicity consists in the<br />

union with God following the purification of the soul and its<br />

illumination by the supernal light.<br />

The meaning of beatitude and its implication for Jewish<br />

culture became a hotly debated issue, constituting the<br />

so-called Maimonidean Controversy of the 13th century. Its<br />

first phase (1202–4) concerned the fate of the human soul after<br />

death and the resurrection of the body; the second phase<br />

(1232–35) was about the composition of Jewish education; the<br />

third phase (c. 1290) pertained to the allegorical interpretation<br />

of the <strong>Torah</strong>; and the fourth (1303–5) to the validity of astrology,<br />

the discipline that most captured scientific naturalism, in<br />

traditional Jewish society. All of these debates were aspects of a<br />

larger question: what is the necessary and sufficient knowledge<br />

for the attainment of the ultimate end of human life defined<br />

as beatitude? The debates were exceptionally acrimonious<br />

because what was at stake was the salvation of the individual<br />

soul, a topic hotly debated not only among Jews but also between<br />

Judaism and Christianity. As Jewish rationalism spread<br />

in Spain, Provençe, and Italy during the 13th century, Jewish<br />

philosophers differentiated between two orders of felicity: one<br />

beatitude<br />

in this world and one of a still higher degree in the hereafter.<br />

This distinction is found in Shem Tov ibn *Falaquera’s Sefer<br />

ha-Ma’alot (ed. L. Venetianer (1894), 15–19), where the “true<br />

happiness of the soul at its ultimate perfection” is said to lead<br />

to the eternal life. <strong>In</strong>voking the notion of a twofold felicity,<br />

*Hillel b. Samuel in his Tagmulei ha-Nefesh (Lyck, 1874) states<br />

that humans, through the perfection of the moral and intellectual<br />

virtues, may achieve a rank even higher than that of<br />

the angels, but the beatific vision becomes possible only after<br />

death. The perfected human is then illumined by the “eternal<br />

light,” rises from rank to rank, and at the end is granted the<br />

vision of God. This state, in Hillel’s view, is the meaning of<br />

Paradise (ibid., 23a–24a). Hillel’s analysis of ultimate felicity<br />

manifests a familiarity with and influence of Christian scholastic<br />

discourse, especially of Thomas *Aquinas.<br />

Jewish philosophers who accepted *Averroes’ epistemology<br />

either openly or implicitly denied the validity of the belief<br />

in individual immortality. Thus, for example, Samuel ibn Tibbon<br />

appears to subscribe to Averroes’ doctrine of the unity of<br />

souls, when in his Ma’amar Yikkavu ha-Mayim (ed. M. Bisliches,<br />

Pressburg, 1837) he says of the soul which has become<br />

perfect and separate from matter at death that it conjoins with<br />

the agent intellect, and that “they become one single thing,<br />

for now the soul becomes divine, of a superior and immortal<br />

order, like the agent intellect with which it is united” (p. 91).<br />

It may be assumed, especially in the light of his commentary<br />

on Ecclesiastes, that Ibn Tibbon speaks here of a “total fusion”<br />

which leaves no room for individual survival (see G. Vajda,<br />

Recherches sur la philosophie et la Kabbale (1962), 27 n. 3).<br />

*Levi b. Gershom, on the other hand, upheld the notion of individual<br />

immortality and of individual degrees of bliss in the<br />

hereafter. <strong>In</strong> his Milḥamot Adonai (1:13) he says that the “degrees<br />

of the happy ones” vary greatly according to the degree<br />

of unity achieved by the acquired intellect in its conception<br />

of the intelligibles. The degree of bliss in the hereafter – identified<br />

by him with Paradise – depends on the degree and type<br />

of knowledge achieved while on earth.<br />

Traditionalist Reaction<br />

The pronounced intellectualism of the philosophers’ concept<br />

of beatitude provoked a great deal of indignant protest from<br />

the traditionalists who regarded the life of piety rather than<br />

intellectual pursuits as the gateway to eternal felicity. The<br />

kabbalist Jacob b. Sheshet *Gerondi (in his Meshiv Deva rim<br />

Nekhoḥim; see Vajda, op. cit., 110–1) attacked Samuel ibn Tibbon’s<br />

interpretation of the ladder in Jacob’s dream as an allegory<br />

of man’s intellectual progress. The Zohar was profoundly<br />

concerned with ultimate felicity and could be viewed as a dramatization<br />

of an ethical theory about the intrinsically good<br />

life as well as an implicit polemic against the systematic discourses<br />

of the rational philosophers. For the Zohar the <strong>Torah</strong><br />

itself is considered as the source of the well-lived life in this<br />

world and the blissful life of the World-to-Come. Unlike the<br />

philosophers, for whom cognizing intelligibles culled from the<br />

observation of nature leads to enlightenment, for the Zohar,<br />

ENCYCLOPAEDIA <strong>JUDAICA</strong>, Second Edition, Volume 3 239

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!