27.10.2014 Views

Russel-Research-Method-in-Anthropology

Russel-Research-Method-in-Anthropology

Russel-Research-Method-in-Anthropology

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Anthropology</strong> and the Social Sciences 9<br />

Bacon and Descartes<br />

Two other figures are often cited as founders of modern scientific th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

Francis Bacon (1561–1626) and René Descartes (1596–1650). Bacon is<br />

known for his emphasis on <strong>in</strong>duction, the use of direct observation to confirm<br />

ideas and the l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g together of observed facts to form theories or explanations<br />

of how natural phenomena work. Bacon correctly never told us how to<br />

get ideas or how to accomplish the l<strong>in</strong>kage of empirical facts. Those activities<br />

rema<strong>in</strong> essentially humanistic—you th<strong>in</strong>k hard.<br />

To Bacon goes the dubious honor of be<strong>in</strong>g the first ‘‘martyr of empiricism.’’<br />

In March 1626, at the age of 65, Bacon was driv<strong>in</strong>g through a rural area north<br />

of London. He had an idea that cold might delay the biological process of<br />

putrefaction, so he stopped his carriage, bought a hen from a local resident,<br />

killed the hen, and stuffed it with snow. Bacon was right—the cold snow did<br />

keep the bird from rott<strong>in</strong>g—but he himself caught bronchitis and died a month<br />

later (Lea 1980).<br />

Descartes didn’t make any systematic, direct observations—he did neither<br />

fieldwork nor experiments—but <strong>in</strong> his Discourse on <strong>Method</strong> (1960 [1637])<br />

and particularly <strong>in</strong> his monumental Meditations (1993 [1641]), he dist<strong>in</strong>guished<br />

between the m<strong>in</strong>d and all external material phenomena—matter—and<br />

argued for what is called dualism <strong>in</strong> philosophy, or the <strong>in</strong>dependent existence<br />

of the physical and the mental world. Descartes also outl<strong>in</strong>ed clearly his vision<br />

of a universal science of nature based on direct experience and the application<br />

of reason—that is, observation and theory. (For more on Descartes’s <strong>in</strong>fluence<br />

on the development of science, see Schuster 1977, Markie 1986, Hausman and<br />

Hausman 1997, and Cott<strong>in</strong>gham 1999.)<br />

Newton<br />

Isaac Newton (1643–1727) pressed the scientific revolution at Cambridge<br />

University. He <strong>in</strong>vented calculus and used it to develop celestial mechanics<br />

and other areas of physics. Just as important, he devised the hypotheticodeductive<br />

model of science that comb<strong>in</strong>es both <strong>in</strong>duction (empirical observation)<br />

and deduction (reason) <strong>in</strong>to a s<strong>in</strong>gle, unified method (Toulm<strong>in</strong> 1980).<br />

In this model, which more accurately reflects how scientists actually conduct<br />

their work, it makes no difference where you get an idea: from data, from<br />

a conversation with your brother-<strong>in</strong>-law, or from just pla<strong>in</strong>, hard, reflexive<br />

th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. What matters is whether you can test your idea aga<strong>in</strong>st data <strong>in</strong> the<br />

real world. This model seems rudimentary to us now, but it is of fundamental<br />

importance and was quite revolutionary <strong>in</strong> the late 17th century.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!