27.10.2014 Views

Russel-Research-Method-in-Anthropology

Russel-Research-Method-in-Anthropology

Russel-Research-Method-in-Anthropology

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

586 Chapter 19<br />

Many researchers use asterisks <strong>in</strong>stead of p-values <strong>in</strong> their writ<strong>in</strong>g to cut<br />

down on number clutter. A s<strong>in</strong>gle asterisk signifies a p-value of .05, a double<br />

asterisk signifies a value of .01 or less, and a triple asterisk signifies a value<br />

of .001 or less. If you read: ‘‘Men were more likely than women** to report<br />

dissatisfaction with local schoolteacher tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g,’’ you’ll know that the double<br />

asterisk means that the difference between men and women on this variable<br />

was significant at the .01 level or better.<br />

And remember: Statistical significance is one th<strong>in</strong>g, but substantive significance<br />

is another matter entirely. In exploratory research, you might be satisfied<br />

with a .10 level of significance. In evaluat<strong>in</strong>g the side effects of a medical<br />

treatment, you might demand a .001 level—or an even more str<strong>in</strong>gent test<br />

of significance.<br />

Type I and Type II Errors<br />

There is one more piece to the logic of hypothesis test<strong>in</strong>g. The choice of an<br />

alpha level lays us open to mak<strong>in</strong>g one of two k<strong>in</strong>ds of error—called, conveniently,<br />

Type I error and Type II error.<br />

If we reject the null hypothesis when it’s really true, that’s a Type I error.<br />

If we fail to reject the null hypothesis when it is, <strong>in</strong> fact, false, that’s a Type<br />

II error.<br />

Suppose we set alpha at .05 and make a Type I error. Our particular sample<br />

produced a mean or a proportion that happened to fall <strong>in</strong> one of the 2.5% tails<br />

of the distribution (2.5% on either side accounts for 5% of all cases), but 95%<br />

of all cases would have resulted <strong>in</strong> a mean that let us reject the null hypothesis.<br />

Suppose the government of a small Caribbean island wants to <strong>in</strong>crease tourism.<br />

To do this, somebody suggests implement<strong>in</strong>g a program to teach restaurant<br />

workers to wash their hands after go<strong>in</strong>g to the bathroom and before return<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to work. The idea is to lower the <strong>in</strong>cidence of food-borne disease and<br />

<strong>in</strong>still confidence among potential tourists.<br />

Suppose you do a pilot study and the results show that H 0 is false at the .05<br />

level of significance. The null hypothesis is that the proposed program is useless,<br />

so this would be great news. But suppose H 0 is really true—the program<br />

really is useless—but you reject it. This Type I error sets off a flurry of activity:<br />

The M<strong>in</strong>istry of Health requires restaurant owners to shell out for the program.<br />

And for what?<br />

The obvious way to guard aga<strong>in</strong>st this Type I error is to raise the bar and<br />

set at, say, .01. That way, a Type I error would be made once <strong>in</strong> a hundred<br />

tries, not five times <strong>in</strong> a hundred. But you see immediately the cost of this little<br />

ploy: It <strong>in</strong>creases dramatically the probability of mak<strong>in</strong>g a Type II error—not

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!