30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Functions of Apollodorus<br />

Matthew D. Walker<br />

In the opening frame prologue of Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>, the enigmatic Apollodorus recounts to an<br />

unnamed companion, and to us, Aristodemus’s story of just what happened at Agathon’s drinking<br />

party. Since Apollodorus did not attend the party, however, it is unclear what relevance he could have<br />

to our understanding of the drama and speeches about erôs that follow. Apollodorus’s strangeness is<br />

accentuated by his recession into the background after only two Stephanus pages. It might seem, then,<br />

that Plato could have presented the <strong>Symposium</strong> without Apollodorus. Instead of writing what David<br />

M. Halperin calls a “mixed narrative” (Apollodorus’s third-person recounting of the events at<br />

Agathon’s party), Plato could always have written a straightforward mimetic account of Agathon’s<br />

party (set in the present tense, in direct discourse), or a first-person report (e.g., from either<br />

Aristodemus’s or Socrates’ point of view). 1 The question thus arises, what difference—if any—does<br />

Apollodorus make to the <strong>Symposium</strong>? Does his inclusion call the dramatic and philosophical unity of<br />

the work into question?<br />

I argue that, despite initial appearances, Plato has important literary and philosophical reasons<br />

for including Apollodorus as a character. Far from being an odd appendage to an otherwise complete<br />

narrative, Apollodorus plays an integral role in the <strong>Symposium</strong>. Of course, one might identify,<br />

piecemeal, any number of functions that Apollodorus could serve in the work. I find it entirely<br />

plausible, for instance, that Plato includes the frame prologue with Apollodorus to render the events<br />

that take place at Agathon’s party mysterious and distant, and to arouse our desire to learn more about<br />

them. 2 In this paper, however, I aim to provide a more systematic account of Apollodorus’s role in the<br />

<strong>Symposium</strong>. Apollodorus, I contend, plays at least four important, interconnected functions in the<br />

work, functions that touch on the <strong>Symposium</strong>’s main themes.<br />

I. Through his portrayal of Apollodorus, who reveals a passion for philosophical logoi, Plato intimates<br />

that erôs, in some way yet to be specified, will (a) somehow be philosophical, or best understood by<br />

reference to philosophizing (φιλοσοφεῖν: 173a3); and that (b) the satisfaction of erôs in philosophy<br />

will somehow be important for securing happiness (or eudaimonia). These claims are central in<br />

Socrates’ own speech concerning erôs. Through his portrayal of Apollodorus, then, Plato primes us to<br />

consider these claims as we go on to read the various speeches concerning erôs that follow. This is the<br />

first function that Apollodorus plays in the <strong>Symposium</strong>.<br />

The thought that erôs is somehow philosophical is developed throughout the speech of<br />

Socrates, which presents the views of Diotima, a Mantinean priestess, and which I take, generally, to<br />

present both Socrates’ and Plato’s own views. According to Socrates’ recounting of Diotima’s<br />

teaching about love (a teaching that personifies erôs in quasi-mythic terms), Erôs—the child of Poros<br />

(Resource) and Penia (Lack)—aims at securing what it lacks and needs (200a-b). Since Erôs aims at<br />

beauty, Erôs lacks beauty. But Erôs is not thereby ugly and bad (201e). Rather, Erôs is an<br />

intermediate spirit, a daimôn who occupies a place in between gods and mortals, beauty and ugliness<br />

(202d-e). Wisdom, however, is among the most beautiful things (204b). Hence, Erôs, lacking beauty,<br />

lacks wisdom. But since Erôs is not altogether ugly, Erôs is not altogether ignorant: Erôs is in between<br />

wisdom and ignorance (203e-204a). Lacking wisdom, but neither ignorant nor foolish, Erôs is a lover<br />

of wisdom—a philosopher (203d6; 204a).<br />

Second, Socrates portrays philosophy as the highest form of erôs, and one whose satisfaction best<br />

secures happiness. Philosophy, that is, is the form of erôs that most completely attains the end at<br />

which erôs aims as such, viz., securing immortal possession of the good through generation. In his<br />

speech, Socrates famously outlines a philosophical ascent, in which the erotic philosopher “moves up”<br />

(ἐπανιὼν: 211b6; cf. of ἐπανιέναι at 211c2) from beautiful particular bodies and souls toward Beauty<br />

itself (αὐτὸ τὸ καλὸν: 211e1). In completing this ascent, and in “contemplating and being with”<br />

(θεωµένου καὶ συνόντος αὐτῷ: 212a2) Beauty itself, the philosopher gives birth to true virtue and<br />

thereby secures a stable, godlike happiness (212a).<br />

The thought that erôs might be philosophical, and might even constitute a kind of erôs, is<br />

striking. Yet such a view might seem far-fetched. The same goes for the thought that one might secure<br />

1 Halperin (1992: 93-129). Cf. Bury (1909: xv-xvi). Translations from the <strong>Symposium</strong> are generally adapted (with<br />

emendations) from Alexander Nehamas and Paul Woodruff’s translation, in Cooper 1997.<br />

2 See Scott and Welton (2008: 28). For her part, Nussbaum (1986: 168) insists that the mixed narrative “makes us always<br />

aware of the fragility of our knowledge of love.”

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!