30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Reproduction, Immortality, and the Greater Mysteries in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong><br />

Thomas M. Tuozzo<br />

What is the philosophical import of Socrates’ contribution to the encomia to Love offered at<br />

Agathon’s dinner party in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>? In this paper I shall offer an answer to this question<br />

which is intended to respond to a trend in recent interpretations of Socrates’ speech in this dialogue.<br />

Scholars have noticed that while what are commonly called “the lesser mysteries” in Diotima’s<br />

teaching put a strong emphasis on immortality through reproduction, the “greater mysteries” make<br />

only one brief mention of immortality. They have accordingly proposed a new interpretation of the<br />

speech: the true culmination of the ascent to the vision of the Beautiful Itself is not, as traditional<br />

readings of the <strong>Symposium</strong> would have it, 1 a self-reproduction that in some sense comes closest to<br />

true immortality, but is rather simply the beatific experience of that vision itself. The concern with<br />

reproduction and immortality, on this view, is an egoistic distortion of the erotic characteristic of the<br />

lesser mysteries; in the greater mysteries the goal is rightly understood as the selfless contemplation of<br />

the Form itself. 2<br />

The question of whether experience of the Beautiful leads one to engage in some activity of<br />

self-reproduction, or is rather a self-contained experience of contemplation, is a manifestation of a<br />

tension in Plato’s philosophy that also shows up in the question of why the philosopher returns to the<br />

cave in the Republic. The tension lives on in Aristotle’s ethics, as the question of the respective roles<br />

of practical and theoretical activity in the highest form of eudaimonia. In my view, speaking very<br />

broadly, for Plato there is always a connection between the soul’s contemplating the eternal principles<br />

of order, the Forms, and its acting in accordance with those principles in shaping the sensible world.<br />

The soul is not a Form, and never can be; its essential temporality is, in fact, one of the central lessons<br />

of the <strong>Symposium</strong>. Plato maintains the connection between the contemplative and the active<br />

dimensions of the grasp of the Forms, even as he emphasizes one or the other in different dialogues.<br />

Indeed, traditionally the Phaedo and the <strong>Symposium</strong> have been seen precisely as complementary<br />

dialogues, stressing, respectively, the other-worldly and this-worldly aspects of knowledge of the<br />

Forms. Recent scholarship has tended to assimilate the <strong>Symposium</strong> to the one-sided view of the<br />

Phaedo; I hope to contest that tendency here.<br />

It is sound move on the part of recent scholars to avoid conflating what Diotima says about<br />

the lesser and the greater mysteries. Socrates’ account of love is in fact clearly articulated into four<br />

sections; ignoring these articulations and indiscriminately mixing together propositions from<br />

throughout his speech is, I think, a recipe for confusion. The first division in Socrates’ account is that<br />

between Socrates’ dialectical exchange with Agathon (199c3-201c9) and his account of the teachings<br />

of Diotima (201d1-212a7). The latter is itself divided into the teachings she gave him on a number of<br />

occasions (201d1-207a4) and the additional teachings she gave on him on one particular occasion<br />

(whether it was ever repeated or not we are not told) (207a5-212a7). This last, finally, is itself divided<br />

into the account of the lesser (207a5-209a4) and the greater mysteries (209a5-212a7). I shall develop<br />

my interpretation by addressing these sections in turn.<br />

Discussion with Agathon<br />

Socrates’ preliminary discussion with Agathon accomplishes more than it appears to at first glance: it<br />

lays the foundation for the extended discussion of the temporality of the soul in the lesser mysteries.<br />

Love, Socrates argues, has an object; Love in fact desires that object; and since desire is for what one<br />

lacks, Love must lack its object. Before specifying what Love’s object is, Socrates considers a<br />

possible objection to the claim that the desirer lacks what he desires: cannot someone who is strong,<br />

or swift, or healthy, or rich, desire to be so, even while possessing the things that make them strong,<br />

swift, etc.? Indeed they can; so Socrates re-interprets what it means to desire what one lacks: it is to<br />

desire to possess something in the future, which, simply in virtue of being in the future, is not yet<br />

available to one. Socrates explicitly extends this analysis to all cases of desire: even in cases where<br />

one desires what one does not presently have, what one desires is not that one presently have it – as<br />

Socrates might say, whether you desire to have it or not, you simply do not have it, and no desire can<br />

change that – but rather that one have it in the future (200e2-5).<br />

1 For a relatively recent, sophisticated version of the traditional interpretation, see Price.<br />

2 Those offering variants of this interpretation include: Ferrarri (1992, 1994), Rowe (1998), Sheffield (2006), and, most<br />

recently, Obdrzalek (2010).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!