30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Gabriel Danzig<br />

(185) Following Bury, he sees the speech as illustrating an interest in mythical allusions and<br />

quotations. 8 But in fact Phaedrus’ speech appears to be highly self-referential.<br />

We know about Phaedrus from several dialogues. Born about 444, he is a very young man in<br />

Protagoras, which is set in 433-2. 9 Evidently interested in intellectual pursuits, he is already<br />

associating with Eryximachos. In Phaedrus he seems to be a slightly older young man (the dramatic<br />

date is uncertain), fascinated by erotikoi logoi. He enjoys hearing speeches in which lovers attempt to<br />

persuade beautiful young men to accept their advances for paradoxical reasons. He appears to be a<br />

popular young man, for we find Socrates following him around and competing jealously with other<br />

offstage intellectuals for his admiration. Although he is not explicitly said to be beautiful, he must<br />

have at least some of the bloom of youth that is necessary for service as an attraction for Socrates<br />

(Symp. 210c1). In one way, the arguments in Phaedrus seem to imply that he is indeed good looking:<br />

Socrates’ explanation of the attractive power of beauty (249e-252c) provides a reflexive explanation<br />

of his pursuit of Phaedrus only on this assumption (see also Diogenes Laertius 3.29).<br />

In <strong>Symposium</strong>, set in 416 when he would be almost thirty years old, Phaedrus shows a similar<br />

interest in the things that lovers do for their beloveds, especially suicides. In more than one way he is<br />

comparable to Critobulus in Xenophon’s <strong>Symposium</strong> who describes at length the services he receives<br />

by virtue of his beauty and the desire this inspires in others (4.10-18). Like Critobulus, Phaedrus<br />

believes that love can contribute to military victory, but in arguing for this case, he goes beyond<br />

Critobulus’ relatively mild comments to suggest sexual relations between the soldiers. 10<br />

How acceptable was Phaedrus’ fascination with eroticism in ancient Athens? Despite the<br />

relative openness of the Greeks concerning erotic subjects, it was not at all common to speak in praise<br />

of eros. Phaedrus has complained to Eryximachos that no one, neither poets nor sophists, has ever<br />

done it before, or rather that no one has dared to do it before (177c: tetolmekenai). 11 This language,<br />

which he also uses in describing the heroism of Achilles (179e) and in contrasting it with the less<br />

impressive behavior of Orpheus (179d), suggests that praising eros requires daring or courage, and<br />

hence that eros was not generally thought to be worthy of praise. Aristophanes also testifies to the<br />

general neglect of this deity (189c). The speakers seem embarrassed to even raise the topic: Phaedrus<br />

does not suggest it openly himself, but turns the task over to Eryximachos, and Eryximachos in turn<br />

makes it clear that the idea is not his own. Hostile attitudes towards pederastic couples are reflected<br />

throughout Pausanias’ speech, and the fact that Socrates merits praise for abstaining from sexual<br />

relations with Alcibiades also shows the low esteem in which they were held. 12<br />

This attitude is not difficult to understand: the Greeks before Plato viewed love as a kind of<br />

mental disease that causes personal and communal disaster. 13 It was responsible in Homer and<br />

Herodotus for catastrophic wars, and in Sophocles and Euripides for suicides and murders. Although a<br />

symposium was a natural place for words of love, there is a difference between giving expression to<br />

the effects of a disease by expressing one’s desire, as in much Greek erotic poetry, and actually<br />

praising the disease while sober. In requesting speeches in praise of eros, Phaedrus is demanding<br />

legitimacy for a subject of great personal interest to him. He wishes his obsession with love to brand<br />

him not as a victim of a mental disease, but as an admirable servant of an important god.<br />

There is a further motive here. Phaedrus is not only a partisan of a disreputable god, he is also<br />

himself an attractive eromenos. 14 As is well known, the passive member of a homosexual relationship<br />

8 R. G. Bury, The <strong>Symposium</strong> of Plato (Cambridge, 1932) xxiv-xxvi); R. Rutherford, The Art of Plato (London, 1995) 190;<br />

R. Hunter, Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong> (Oxford, 2004) 38-42.<br />

9 See D. Nails, People of Plato (Indianapolis, 1992) 233-4.<br />

10 This is one of the chief arguments for the priority of at least this section of Xenophon’s <strong>Symposium</strong>: it is hard to imagine<br />

Xenophon copying from Plato and attributing to Critobulus a mild version of a suggestion that he evidently finds so<br />

objectionable (see 8.33-4).<br />

11 Phaedrus himself seems embarrassed to raise his suggestion in public and has apparently asked Eryximachos to do so on<br />

his behalf; and Eryximachos, while willing to raise the suggestion, does not take responsibility for it, but mentions its real<br />

author. The fact that this subject was somewhat off-limits by the fourth century may also explain the many-layered literary<br />

frame and the intense curiosity that is evoked in the opening conversation.<br />

12 The off-bounds character of erotic matters is also reflected in the secretive way that Phaedrus treats the speech of Lysias<br />

in Phaedrus (228d-e). This may also explain the great curiosity that the subject evidently arouses at the time of the telling of<br />

<strong>Symposium</strong> (172a-173d). T. K. Hubbard has suggested that attitudes towards homosexuality underwent a change in the<br />

middle and late fifth century (“Pederasty and Democracy: The Marginalization of a Social Practice,” in T. K. Hubbard, ed.,<br />

Greek Love Reconsidered, New York, 2000, 1-11. If so, the elaborate chain of transmission of the contents of <strong>Symposium</strong><br />

may be designed to reflect a memory of a time when pederasty was more widely favored.<br />

13 Although it needs to be used with caution, the most comprehensive treatment of this point is Bruce S. Thornton, Eros: The<br />

Myth of Ancient Greek Sexuality (Boulder, Colorado, 1997). This attitude did not change quickly: despite Plato’s efforts to<br />

make eros into a respectable subject, Aristotle barely mentions it in his own vast ethical writings.<br />

14 Although typically the eromenos was a young man without a beard, in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong> this role is played by men who<br />

would have been about the age of thirty, such as Agathon and Alcibiades. It is not clear to me how much we are meant to<br />

357

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!