30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Gabriel Danzig<br />

Pausanias<br />

As a devoted lover of Agathon (Protagoras 315d-e; see also X. Mem. 8.32), Pausanias shares<br />

with Phaedrus the general aim of dispelling the stigma that attaches to eros. 19 He is the first speaker to<br />

claim that homosexual love is superior to heterosexual love, an opinion that must not have been<br />

universally accepted if he has to argue for it (see 181c). Like Phaedrus, Pausanias is concerned with<br />

popular attitudes and he uses some form of the word nomos not less than 21 times between 181d and<br />

184e. As an erastes, Pausanias suffered from a different kind of hostility than that to which an<br />

eromenos was exposed. While the eromenos suffered from the humiliation of being used like a<br />

woman, the erastes was considered an enemy by the friends and family of his supposed victims (see<br />

183c-d).<br />

Pausanias defends himself by accepting the views of his opponents to a large degree. There<br />

are men who should be kept away from boys, especially very young ones, but he is not among them.<br />

He hopes to redeem the reputations of virtuous pederasts such as himself and to encourage potential<br />

young eromenoi to choose the right sort of lovers. The better sort love boys for their souls or intellects,<br />

and hence have no interest in girls or very young boys, neither of whom have much intellect to love<br />

(181c). 20 They love slightly older boys whose intellects are starting to bloom and they tend to stick<br />

with them for a long time. He thinks it is wrong to castigate those who engage in pederastic relations<br />

in the right way, arguing that it is only the inferior lovers who give pederasty a bad name (182a). He<br />

takes the high moral ground by proclaiming that there should be a law against those who take<br />

advantage of young boys (paidōn: 181d-e), but it is surprising to see who this law is meant to protect.<br />

Pausanias argues that the pederasts are the ones who are harmed by the young boys they pursue, since<br />

young boys are apt to turn out disappointing (181e). His parallel, the sanctions against sexual relations<br />

with unmarried free women (181e-182a), would not support this explanation. But it fits well his effort<br />

to gain sympathy for the older lover.<br />

As Pausanias notes, parents are deeply concerned about the effects pederasty may have on<br />

their young children and take serious efforts to prevent its occurrence (183c-d). Understandably,<br />

Pausanias spends much less time on this than he does describing the encouragement that is given to<br />

those who pursue beautiful young men (182d-183c). These conflicting attitudes need reflect nothing<br />

other than the fact that plenty of men in Athens, including the very fathers who objected to the<br />

pederastic use of their sons, would have been quite happy to form a sexual relationship with a nice<br />

young boy from another family: what is good for me may not be good for you. But Pausanias, finding<br />

a deeper logic in them, argues that Athenians take a moderate stance towards pederasty, neither<br />

outlawing it, as is done in barbaric (ie., non-Greek but also uncivilized) and tyrannous regimes, nor<br />

enforcing it, as is done in societies whose members, according to him, lack the wit to properly seduce<br />

a boy. Its complex and seemingly contradictory attitudes – encouraging the lover while discouraging<br />

the boy – are actually designed to insure that the young people will form sexual relations with<br />

excellent men like himself.<br />

The speech seems like an advertisement for these better lovers, and hence for Pausanias<br />

himself. He argues that the better lovers contribute to the acquisition of virtue and wisdom by the<br />

boys (184c-185c), and he also puts great emphasis on the fact that the better lovers are willing to<br />

devote themselves to their beloveds for the long-term (183e-184b) 21 as he apparently did with<br />

Agathon. 22 But although Pausanias devotes much of his effort to praising those who love boys for<br />

their souls rather than their bodies, he does not encourage what we call “platonic” relationships. It is<br />

important to him that the boys he seduces reciprocate his affection by offering their bodies for his<br />

gratification, and he insists that young men give their bodies only to those who, like himself, love<br />

them for their souls (tois men charizesthai, tous de phugein: 184a). Nor does Pausanias place any limit<br />

on the kind of sexual activities that may legitimately take place. As he says, there is no act that is<br />

inherently prohibited; it all depends on how it is done (181a). The analogies he offers, of drinking,<br />

singing and talking, suggest that he is referring to specific acts that lovers engage in with their<br />

beloveds. The better lover does not refrain from any of these acts, but rather performs them in a fine<br />

19 Many theories have been proposed to explain the order of the speeches in <strong>Symposium</strong> (see Bury, lii-lvii). I believe that<br />

each speech is paired both with the one before it, if there is one, and with the one after it, if there is one.<br />

20 While boys are more attractive intellectually than girls, there is no claim that they are more beautiful physically. In<br />

Xenophon’s Cyropaedia (5.1.7) and Memorabilia (3.11) women are presented as the most beautiful temptations.<br />

21 Pausanias’ and Agathon’s long-term love affair played an important role in the introduction of this principle which was to<br />

play a fundamental role in Aristotle’s thinking on friendship and in the thinking of the entire philosophic tradition in the west<br />

and its associated cultures during the thousands of years that followed.<br />

22 There may be something defensive in this latter claim, since his long-term relationship with Agathon was made into a<br />

subject of ridicule in Athens. See L. Brisson, “Agathon, Pausanias, and Diotima in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>: Paiderastia and<br />

Philosophia,” in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>, ed. J. Lesher et al., Washington, 2006, 229-251.<br />

359

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!