30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

ABSTRACT<br />

Platonic Fables as Philosophical Poiesis<br />

Rick Benitez<br />

Scholars have sometimes noted the importance of fables to Plato by pointing to the passage of Phaedo<br />

in which Cebes speaks of Socrates embellishing Aesop's fables (ἐντείνας τοὺς τοῦ Αἰσώπου λόγους,<br />

60d1). Some have suggested that Plato's fables play an important structural role in the philosophical<br />

lessons of particular dialogues (e.g. Betegh, 2009). 1 None, however, have gone so far as to describe<br />

the Platonic fables as making an important contribution to Plato's critique of poetry generally. In this<br />

paper I propose that Platonic fables—short myths, typically incorporating comic elements and<br />

embedding a philosophical lesson rather than a caution—have a cognitive function that conventional<br />

fables do not: they reflect a rationally ordered picture of how things are. Mimesis of a rational order<br />

of things is an aesthetic criterion; we see it at work in Plato's fables, where it provides a model for<br />

what Plato believes good poems and myths should do.<br />

A unique context for examining my hypothesis is the <strong>Symposium</strong>, because it presents both a<br />

Platonic fable—the fable of Poros and Penia—and a fable in conventional form—Aristophanes' fable<br />

of the circle-men. In the <strong>Symposium</strong> it is possible to observe both Plato's objections to conventional<br />

fables and his recommendations for what fables (and by extension poems and myths) should do.<br />

Scholars have generally treated the fable of Poros and Penia as part of Socrates' response to Agathon,<br />

but there are many similarities to Aristophanes' fable (such as the union of complementary beings, the<br />

neediness of incomplete beings, the relationship of desire to lack, etc.). Despite the structural<br />

similarities linking the two fables, however, they function in entirely different ways. While<br />

Aristophanes' fable emphasises the irrationality of the human condition, the hubris of human beings,<br />

and the need to fear the gods because of their power to destroy, the fable of Poros and Penia<br />

emphasises cognitive capacities, approves of unrestrained desire to understand, and establishes<br />

intercourse between humans and gods through an intermediate.<br />

Hunter (2004:85) 2 recognised that the fable of Poros and Penia provides part of the<br />

philosophical education of the acolyte of beauty (though according to him only the lowest part). My<br />

aim in this paper is to show that the Poros and Penia fable does more than that. Since it incorporates<br />

an understanding of the nature, object and function of desire, it is the sort of story that only a teacher<br />

who had received the highest vision could tell. It is thus a creation that is born in the presence of the<br />

beautiful—the sort of creation that reflects how things really are. The fable of Poros and Penia, then,<br />

is not only an inducement to the attainment of rational vision, it is the accomplishment of such a<br />

vision.<br />

Sheffield (2006:45) 3 has noted that through the fable of Poros and Penia "Socrates envisages<br />

stories with the right (philosophical) content." This is correct, but does not go far enough. The fable<br />

also allows us to envisage stories with the right form and aim of composition.<br />

1 Gabor Betegh, 2009, "Tale, theology and teleology in the Phaedo" in Catalin Partenie, ed., Plato's Myths. Cambridge.<br />

2 Richard Hunter, 2004, Plato's <strong>Symposium</strong>, Oxford.<br />

3 Frisbee Sheffield, 2006, Plato's <strong>Symposium</strong>: The Ethics of Desire, Oxford.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!