30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Olga Alieva<br />

difference between the two; finally, both texts deal with χαρίζεσθαι ἐρασταῖς motif and are<br />

fallaciously reasoned. 24 But Pausanias’ speech has one important novelty as compared to the Dissoi<br />

logoi, namely the protreptic element.<br />

Pausanias is not interested in defending the paradoxical thesis that µὴ ἐραστᾶι χαρίζεσθαι καλόν; he<br />

aims at more: it is only noble to gratify a lover for the sake of wisdom and moral perfection (see<br />

above texts 6, 8) 25 . The pursuit of virtue justifies, in his opinion, δουλεία ἑκούσιος (184c2; cfr.<br />

ἐθελοδουλεία 184c2-7). In full compliance with this practice, Alcibiades wants to gratify<br />

(218d4: χαριζόµενος) Socrates in order to become better (218d2: βέλτιστον …γενέσθαι).<br />

In the Euthydemus, 26 where Socrates invents his own protrpetic, the interlocutors are driven to the<br />

conclusion that there’s no disgrace in being a slave for the sake of wisdom (282b 27 ). Narcy justly<br />

observes that in both cases the use of the verb προτρέπω recurs in a context where the case in point is<br />

the exceptional value of wisdom. Philosophical protreptic therefore involves what Narcy labels as<br />

“monopoly on seduction”. I’ll try to demonstrate that such understanding stems from Antisthenes, to<br />

whom Plato playfully alludes in the <strong>Symposium</strong>.<br />

Antisthenes: ἀξιέραστος ὁ σοφός<br />

The extant fragments of Antisthenes abound in scornful remarks concerning “worldly” love and<br />

pleasure. “I would rather go mad than enjoy pleasure”; 28 “If I could catch Aphrodite I would shoot her<br />

with my bow, because she has corrupted so many excellent and beautiful women among us” (SSR V<br />

A 122−123) 29 and so on.<br />

On the other hand, as Kahn puts it, Antisthenes “has a much more positive conception of<br />

philosophical eros in the sense of intimate friendship among intellectuals in pursuit of virtue.” 30 Thus,<br />

he says: “the wise man will be in love for he is the only one who knows whom one should love” (SSR<br />

V A 58 = DL VI 11 31 ) and “it is the sage who is worthy of love and friend to one like himself” (SSR<br />

V A 99 = DL VI 105 32 ).<br />

It is difficult to account for these inconsistencies unless we assume that Antisthenes distinguished<br />

between the two Eroses: a vulgar one and a philosophical one, just like Pausanias does. This<br />

assumption is indirectly corroborated by a passage from Xenophon’s <strong>Symposium</strong> (VIII. 10) where<br />

Socrates draws a distinction between the vulgar and the heavenly Aphrodite. 33<br />

Furthermore, it is likely that in Antisthenes eros was endowed with educational function. The above<br />

cited fragment from Diogenes Laertius (see note 32: ἀξιέραστος ὁ σοφός) is taken from the writing<br />

Heracles where Antisthenes showed τὴν ἀρετὴν διδακτὴν εἶναι. There, Heracles was depicted as one<br />

to gratify lovers”; “in Ionia and many other regions where they live under foreign sway, it is counted a disgrace”. The latter<br />

practice is then associated with the despotic rule peculiar to the barbarians (text 3).<br />

24<br />

Pausanias’ argument is circular: if there is nothing noble or base “by itself”, any “manner” under certain circumstances<br />

can be regarded as either noble or ignoble. Besides, there is a fallacious slip: what is “by itself” neither noble nor base turns<br />

out to be indispensable for attaining moral virtue.<br />

25<br />

See note 54. However, with “wisdom” he means no more than persuasiveness in speech. See: Rosen, op. cit., 89.<br />

26<br />

Michelini notes certain parallelism between the protreptic in the Euthydemus and Pausanias’ speech; see: Michelini, A.,<br />

“Socrates Plays the Buffoon: Cautionary Protreptic in Euthydemus”, American Journal of Philology 121 (2000), 509-35.<br />

Rappe argues that the Euthydemus “exhibits a number of familiar Cynic trademarks, or rather motifs that strikingly<br />

anticipate Cynicism, (apparently) associated with Socrates’ follower Antisthenes”; see: Rappe, S., “Father of the dogs?<br />

Tracking the Cynics in Plato’s Euthydemus”, Classical Philology, 95, 3 (2000), 282-303. On Antisthenes’ Protreptic see our<br />

paper in the Socratica III volume “Protreptic in the Socratics: In Search of a Genre” (in print).<br />

27<br />

Narcy, op.cit., 114. On slavery for the sake of virtue as a protreptic motif see: Slings, S.R., Plato, Clitophon, Cambridge<br />

(UK), 1999, 117-118.<br />

28<br />

Translation is cited from: Kahn, Ch., “Plato as a Socratic”, in Hommage à Henri Joly, Recherches sur la Philosophie et le<br />

Langage 12, Grenoble, 1990, 287-301, here 289.<br />

29<br />

See especially Theodoret. Graec. Aff. Cur. III. 53 (SSR V A 123): αὐτίκα τοίνυν ᾿Αντισθένης ὁ Σωκράτους ἑταῖρος καὶ<br />

Διογένους διδάσκαλος, τὴν σωφροσύνην περὶ πλείστου ποιούµενος καὶ τὴν ἡδονὴν µυσαττόµενος, τοιάδε περὶ τῆς<br />

᾿Αφροδίτης λέγεται φάναι «ἐγὼ δὲ τὴν ᾿Αφροδίτην κἂν κατατοξεύσαιµι, εἰ λάβοιµι, ὅτι πολλὰς ἡµῶν καλὰς κἀγαθὰς<br />

γυναῖκας διέφθειρεν». τὸν δέ γε ἔρωτα κακίαν ἐκάλει τῆς φύσεως, ἧς ἥττους ὄντες οἱ κακοδαίµονες θεὸν τὴν νόσον<br />

καλοῦσιν. ταύτῃ τοι µανῆναι µᾶλλον ἢ ἡσθῆναι ᾑρεῖτο.<br />

30<br />

Kahn, “Plato as a Socratic”, 289.<br />

31<br />

DL VI 11: (τὸν σοφὸν) γαµήσειν τε τεκνοποιίας χάριν, ταῖς εὐφυεστάταις συνιόντα γυναιξί. καὶ ἐρασθήσεσθαι δέ· µόνον<br />

γὰρ εἰδέναι τὸν σοφὸν τίνων χρὴ ἐρᾶν.<br />

32<br />

DL VI 105: Ἀρέσκει δ' αὐτοῖς καὶ τὴν ἀρετὴν διδακτὴν εἶναι, καθά φησιν Ἀντισθένης ἐν τῷ Ἡρακλεῖ, καὶ ἀναπόβλητον<br />

ὑπάρχειν· ἀξιέραστόν τε τὸν σοφὸν καὶ ἀναµάρτητον καὶ φίλον τῷ ὁµοίῳ, τύχῃ τε µηδὲν ἐπιτρέπειν.<br />

33<br />

Kahn remarks that though this passage “has certainly been influenced by Pausanias’ speech in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>”,<br />

“Xenophon’s distinction between carnal and noble eros is much more simplistic than anything in Plato” and “it probably<br />

reflects Antisthenes’ distinction between the bad eros based on pleasure” and “the morally sound eros based upon virtue and<br />

wisdom in the beloved.” See: Kahn, “Plato as a Socratic”, 290.<br />

156

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!