30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

ABSTRACT<br />

The Kind of Knowledge Virtue Is:<br />

Rational Ecstasy in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong><br />

Kendall Sharp<br />

At the close of Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>, Socrates is seen “compelling [Agathon and Aristophanes] to agree<br />

that it belongs to the same man to know how to make [epistasthai poein] comedy and tragedy, and the<br />

man who is a tragedy-maker by technê is also a comedy-maker” (223d). This scene evokes Socrates’<br />

argument, from Ion, that the poets’ knowledge is not a technê but a divine gift. Two other dialogues,<br />

Protagoras and Meno, also end on the related theme that virtue, although knowledge, cannot be taught<br />

by instruction like technê-knowledge (Protagoras), and comes to people by divine gift (Meno). Yet<br />

Socrates in Ion and Phaedrus describes divinely inspired knowledge as a type of mania. Two urgent<br />

questions thus arise: If not by instruction, then how do humans acquire by divine gift the knowledge<br />

that is virtue? Second, if this knowledge comes by divine gift, then why is virtue not a type of<br />

madness? In this paper, I argue that by concluding with this scene, Plato associates <strong>Symposium</strong> with<br />

these questions, and indicates that he has answered them in the speeches of Socrates and Alcibiades.<br />

In these speeches, Plato sets forth a picture about the kind of divinely inspired knowledge virtue is,<br />

and about Socrates’ role in helping others obtain it by divine gift and become virtuous.<br />

The picture emerges when the two speeches are read in light of our two questions. While<br />

virtue is not technê-knowledge, Socrates claims another type of knowledge, which he calls “ta<br />

erôtika” (Smp. 177d, 198d). Socrates’ speech can be read as answering our two questions by<br />

describing this erotic knowledge. This knowledge fits the bill because it comes by divine gift (Lysis<br />

204bc), but leaves its recipients in their right minds nevertheless, for it results in part from extensive<br />

training in rational discourse (logoi) (Smp. 210a-d). Alcibiades in his speech makes clear that this<br />

training in rational discourse consists in precisely Socrates’ characteristic conversational practice. He<br />

also displays the non-technê, divine aspect of this knowledge in his own experience of it. Not only<br />

does he inadvertently echo Socrates’ use of metaphors from the mystery religions. Alcibiades’ speech<br />

also connects Socrates’ eulogy of Eros to his model in Ion for sharing divine inspiration. In that<br />

dialogue, Socrates describes how the poet’s divine inspiration is obtained, not through instruction like<br />

a technê, but during moments of personal contact with one who already possesses the gift (535e-<br />

536d). This matches very closely how Alcibiades describes the beneficial influence of Socrates on<br />

himself, as turning him to philosophy only when he is in Socrates’ presence. When he is not with<br />

Socrates, this beneficial influence fades, and Alcibiades’ focus shifts back to his more usual political<br />

ambitions (216a-b). If Socrates’ speech is understood as answering our two questions, then the<br />

knowledge that is virtue is erotic knowledge of to kalon. At different degrees of initiation, this<br />

knowledge comes by divine gift to those who philosophize, but only after the soul is prepared by<br />

training in the rational logoi of Socrates’ conversational practice (210a-e).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!